Difference between revisions of "Speech"

From No Subject - Encyclopedia of Psychoanalysis
Jump to: navigation, search
 
Line 1: Line 1:
 +
speech (parole)           
  
speech (parole)            The French term parole presents considerable difficulty
+
The French term parole presents considerable difficulty to the English translator because it does not correspond to any one English word. In some contexts it corresponds to the English term 'speech', and in others is best translated as 'word'.
  
to the English translator because it does not correspond to any one English
+
Parole becomes one of the most important terms in Lacan's work from the early 1950s on. In his famous 'Rome discourse', Lacan denounces the way that the role of speech in psychoanalysis had come to be neglected by contemporary psychoanalytic theory, and argues for a renewed focus on speech and LANGUAGE (Lacan, 1953a). Lacan's use of the term parole owes little to Saussure (whose opposition between parole and langue is replaced in Lacan's work with the opposition between parole and langage), and is far more determined by references to anthropology, theology, and metaphysics.
  
word. In some contexts it corresponds to the English term 'speech', and in
+
Anthropology       
 +
Lacan's concept of speech as a 'symbolic exchange' which 'links human beings to each other' (Sl, 142) is clearly influenced by the work of Mauss and LÈvi-Strauss, especially their analysis of the exchange of gifts. Thus Freud's interpretations are described as 'a symbolic gift of speech, pregnant with      a secret pact' (E, 79). The concept of speech as a pact which assigns roles to both the addressee and the addresser is formulated in Lacan's concept of FOUNDING SPEECH.
  
others is best translated as 'word'.
+
Theology
 +
Speech also takes on religious and theological connotations in Lacan's work, in terms derived both from Eastern religions (E, 106-7) and the Judaeo-Christian tradition (E, 106). In 1954, Lacan discusses speech with reference to St Augustine's De locutionis significatione (Sl, 247-60). Like the words uttered by God in Genesis, speech is a 'symbolic invocation' which creates, ex nihilo, 'a new order of being in the relations between men' (Sl, 239).
  
      Parole becomes one of the most important terms in Lacan's work from the
+
Metaphysics       
 +
Lacan draws on Heidegger's distinction between Rede (discourse) and Gerede (chatter) to elaborate his own distinction between 'full speech' (parole pleine) and 'empty speech' (parole vide) (see E, 40ff.). Lacan first makes this distinction in 1953, and though it no longer plays an important part in his work after 1955, it never disappears completely. Full speech articulates the symbolic dimension of language, whereas empty speech articulates the imaginary dimension of language, the speech from the ego to the counterpart. 'Full speech is a speech full of meaning [sens]. Empty speech is a speech which has only signification' (Lacan, 1976--7; Ornicar?, nos 17/18: 11).
  
 +
Full speech is also called 'true speech', since it is closer to the enigmatic truth of the subject's desire: 'Full speech is speech which aims at, which forms, the truth such as it becomes established in the recognition of one person by another. Full speech is speech which performs [qui fait acte]' (Sl, 107). 'Full speech, in effect, is defined by its identity with that which it speaks about' (Ec, 381).
  
 +
In empty speech, on the other hand, the subject is alienated from his desire; in empty speech 'the subject seems to be talking in vain about someone who  . .  . can never become one with the assumption of his desire' (E, 45).
  
 +
One of the analyst's tasks when listening to the analysand is to discern the moments when full speech emerges. Full speech and empty speech are the extreme points on a continuum, and 'between these two extremes, a whole gamut of modes of realisation of speech is deployed' (Sl, 50). The aim of psychoanalytic treatment is to articulate full speech, which is hard work; full speech can be quite laborious (pÈnible) to articulate (E, 253).
  
 +
Empty speech is not the same as lying; on the contrary, lies often reveal the TRUTH about desire more fully than many honest statements (see Sll, 139-40).
  
early 1950s on. In his famous 'Rome discourse', Lacan denounces the way that
+
It is never possible to articulate in speech the whole truth of one's desire, because of a fundamental 'incompatibility between desire and speech' (E, 275); 'I always tell the truth; not the whole truth, because we are not capable of telling it all. Telling it all is materially impossible' (Lacan, 1973a: 9). Full speech, then, is not the articulation in speech of the whole truth about the subject's desire, but the speech which articulates this truth as fully as possible at a particular time.
 
+
Speech is the only means of access to the truth about desire; 'speech alone is the key to that truth' (E, 172). Moreover, psychoanalytic theory claims that it is only a particular kind of speech that leads to this truth; a speech without conscious control, known as free association.
the role of speech in psychoanalysis had come to be neglected by contempor-
 
 
 
ary psychoanalytic theory, and argues for a renewed focus on speech and
 
 
 
LANGUAGE (Lacan, 1953a). Lacan's    use of the term parole      owes little to
 
 
 
Saussure (whose opposition between parole and langue is replaced in Lacan's
 
 
 
work with the opposition between parole and langage), and is far more
 
 
 
determined by references to anthropology, theology, and metaphysics.
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
  e Anthropology        Lacan's concept of speech      as  a 'symbolic exchange'
 
 
 
which 'links human beings to each other' (Sl, 142) is clearly influenced by
 
 
 
the work of Mauss and LÈvi-Strauss, especially their analysis of the exchange
 
 
 
of gifts. Thus Freud's interpretations are described as 'a symbolic gift of
 
 
 
speech, pregnant with      a secret pact' (E, 79). The concept of speech as          a
 
 
 
pact which assigns roles to both the addressee and the addresser is formulated
 
 
 
in Lacan's concept of FOUNDING SPEECH.
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
  e Theology Speech also takes on religious and theological connotations in
 
 
 
Lacan's work, in terms derived both from Eastern religions (E, 106-7) and the
 
 
 
Judaeo-Christian tradition (E, 106). In 1954, Lacan discusses speech with
 
 
 
reference to St Augustine's De locutionis significatione (Sl, 247-60). Like
 
 
 
the words uttered by God in Genesis, speech is a 'symbolic invocation' which
 
 
 
creates, ex nihilo, 'a new order of being in the relations between men' (Sl, 239).
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
  ï Metaphysics        Lacan draws    on Heidegger's distinction between Rede
 
 
 
(discourse) and Gerede (chatter) to elaborate his own distinction between
 
 
 
'full speech' (parole pleine) and 'empty speech' (parole vide) (see E, 40ff.).
 
 
 
Lacan first makes this distinction in 1953, and though it no longer plays an
 
 
 
important part in his work after 1955, it never disappears completely. Full
 
 
 
speech articulates the symbolic dimension of language, whereas empty speech
 
 
 
articulates the imaginary dimension of language, the speech from the ego to
 
 
 
the counterpart. 'Full speech is a speech full of meaning [sens]. Empty speech
 
 
 
is a speech which has only signification' (Lacan, 1976--7; Ornicar?, nos 17/18:
 
 
 
11).
 
 
 
      Full speech is also called 'true speech', since it is closer to the enigmatic
 
 
 
truth of the subject's desire: 'Full speech is speech which aims at, which forms,
 
 
 
the truth such as it becomes established in the recognition of one person by
 
 
 
another. Full speech is speech which performs [qui fait acte]' (Sl, 107). 'Full
 
 
 
speech, in effect, is defined by its identity with that which it speaks about' (Ec,
 
 
 
381).
 
 
 
      In empty speech, on the other hand, the subject is alienated from his desire;
 
 
 
in empty speech 'the subject seems to be talking in vain about someone who
 
 
 
  . .  . can never become one with the assumption of his desire' (E, 45).
 
 
 
      One of the analyst's tasks when listening to the analysand is to discern the
 
 
 
moments when full speech emerges. Full speech and empty speech are the
 
 
 
extreme points on a continuum, and 'between these two extremes, a whole
 
 
 
 
 
gamut of modes of realisation of speech is deployed' (Sl, 50). The aim of
 
 
 
psychoanalytic treatment is to articulate full speech, which is hard work; full
 
 
 
speech can be quite laborious (pÈnible) to articulate (E, 253).
 
 
 
      Empty speech is not the same as lying; on the contrary, lies often reveal the
 
 
 
  TRUTH about desire more fully than many honest statements (see Sll, 139-40).
 
 
 
It is never possible to articulate in speech the whole truth of one's desire,
 
 
 
because of a fundamental 'incompatibility between desire and speech' (E,
 
 
 
275); 'I always tell the truth; not the whole truth, because we are not capable
 
 
 
of telling it all. Telling it all is materially impossible' (Lacan, 1973a: 9). Full
 
 
 
speech, then, is not the articulation in speech of the whole truth about the
 
 
 
subject's desire, but the speech which articulates this truth as fully as possible
 
 
 
  at a particular time.
 
 
 
      Speech is the only means of access to the truth about desire; 'speech alone is
 
 
 
the key to that truth' (E, 172). Moreover, psychoanalytic theory claims that it
 
 
 
is only a particular kind of speech that leads to this truth; a speech without
 
 
 
conscious control, known as free association.
 
 
 
  
 +
speech 18, 126-7, 129, 133, 149, 188, 198, 228, 245, 269, 271, 278 [[Seminar XI]]
  
  

Revision as of 07:06, 22 May 2006

speech (parole)

The French term parole presents considerable difficulty to the English translator because it does not correspond to any one English word. In some contexts it corresponds to the English term 'speech', and in others is best translated as 'word'.

Parole becomes one of the most important terms in Lacan's work from the early 1950s on. In his famous 'Rome discourse', Lacan denounces the way that the role of speech in psychoanalysis had come to be neglected by contemporary psychoanalytic theory, and argues for a renewed focus on speech and LANGUAGE (Lacan, 1953a). Lacan's use of the term parole owes little to Saussure (whose opposition between parole and langue is replaced in Lacan's work with the opposition between parole and langage), and is far more determined by references to anthropology, theology, and metaphysics.

Anthropology Lacan's concept of speech as a 'symbolic exchange' which 'links human beings to each other' (Sl, 142) is clearly influenced by the work of Mauss and LÈvi-Strauss, especially their analysis of the exchange of gifts. Thus Freud's interpretations are described as 'a symbolic gift of speech, pregnant with a secret pact' (E, 79). The concept of speech as a pact which assigns roles to both the addressee and the addresser is formulated in Lacan's concept of FOUNDING SPEECH.

Theology Speech also takes on religious and theological connotations in Lacan's work, in terms derived both from Eastern religions (E, 106-7) and the Judaeo-Christian tradition (E, 106). In 1954, Lacan discusses speech with reference to St Augustine's De locutionis significatione (Sl, 247-60). Like the words uttered by God in Genesis, speech is a 'symbolic invocation' which creates, ex nihilo, 'a new order of being in the relations between men' (Sl, 239).

Metaphysics Lacan draws on Heidegger's distinction between Rede (discourse) and Gerede (chatter) to elaborate his own distinction between 'full speech' (parole pleine) and 'empty speech' (parole vide) (see E, 40ff.). Lacan first makes this distinction in 1953, and though it no longer plays an important part in his work after 1955, it never disappears completely. Full speech articulates the symbolic dimension of language, whereas empty speech articulates the imaginary dimension of language, the speech from the ego to the counterpart. 'Full speech is a speech full of meaning [sens]. Empty speech is a speech which has only signification' (Lacan, 1976--7; Ornicar?, nos 17/18: 11).

Full speech is also called 'true speech', since it is closer to the enigmatic truth of the subject's desire: 'Full speech is speech which aims at, which forms, the truth such as it becomes established in the recognition of one person by another. Full speech is speech which performs [qui fait acte]' (Sl, 107). 'Full speech, in effect, is defined by its identity with that which it speaks about' (Ec, 381).

In empty speech, on the other hand, the subject is alienated from his desire; in empty speech 'the subject seems to be talking in vain about someone who . . . can never become one with the assumption of his desire' (E, 45).

One of the analyst's tasks when listening to the analysand is to discern the moments when full speech emerges. Full speech and empty speech are the extreme points on a continuum, and 'between these two extremes, a whole gamut of modes of realisation of speech is deployed' (Sl, 50). The aim of psychoanalytic treatment is to articulate full speech, which is hard work; full speech can be quite laborious (pÈnible) to articulate (E, 253).

Empty speech is not the same as lying; on the contrary, lies often reveal the TRUTH about desire more fully than many honest statements (see Sll, 139-40).

It is never possible to articulate in speech the whole truth of one's desire, because of a fundamental 'incompatibility between desire and speech' (E, 275); 'I always tell the truth; not the whole truth, because we are not capable of telling it all. Telling it all is materially impossible' (Lacan, 1973a: 9). Full speech, then, is not the articulation in speech of the whole truth about the subject's desire, but the speech which articulates this truth as fully as possible at a particular time. Speech is the only means of access to the truth about desire; 'speech alone is the key to that truth' (E, 172). Moreover, psychoanalytic theory claims that it is only a particular kind of speech that leads to this truth; a speech without conscious control, known as free association.

speech 18, 126-7, 129, 133, 149, 188, 198, 228, 245, 269, 271, 278 Seminar XI


References