Changes

Jump to: navigation, search

Anarchy

360 bytes added, 18:19, 27 May 2019
The LinkTitles extension automatically added links to existing pages (https://github.com/bovender/LinkTitles).
It is precisely this emphasis on the primacy of the political that also characterizes anarchism. Anarchism offered a radical alternative to Marxism by insisting on the importance and autonomy of the political realm - in particular, the specific [[power]] and authority of the State institution - rather than subsuming it, as classical Marxism did, to an [[analysis]] of the [[economy]] and class relations. Anarchism therefore offered new theoretical tools for the analysis of political power, beyond the [[economic]] and class reductionism of Marxism. Its major theoretical [[achievement]] was precisely to unmask both the specific and [[autonomous]] dimension of political authority, and the dangers of their reaffirmation in a [[revolution]] if neglected. In [[other]] words, power and authority were now seen as phenomena that could no longer be reduced to their different class articulations. Rather, they were to be [[understood]] in terms of an abstract [[position]] or [[place]] in the social, and as having their own structural imperative - that of [[self]]-perpetuation - which instantiated itself in different guises, including that of the [[Marxist]] [[workers]]' revolution itself. Therefore, the [[place of power]] could not be easily overcome, and was always in [[danger]] of [[being]] reaffirmed unless addressed specifically. Anarchism thus exposed the limitations of Marxist theory in dealing with the problem of power and authority. Blinded as it was by its economic determinism, Marxism failed to see power and authority as phenomena that were irreducible to economic factors, requiring their own specific forms of analysis. Anarchism, moreover, pointed to other sites of authority and domination that were neglected in Marxist theory - for example, the [[Church]], the [[family]] and patriarchal [[structures]], [[technology]], as well as the [[structure]] and hierarchy of the revolutionary party itself.
Anarchism is an [[enlightenment]]-based radical political [[philosophy]], at the heart of which is a [[dialectical]] relationship between freedom and authority. The possibilities of [[human]] freedom, according to anarchist theory have their basis in an essential [[rational]] [[harmony]] that has been disrupted by the operation of "artificial" political authority. However, this harmony constitutes the [[objective]] [[truth]] of social relations - a truth that lies dormant, waiting to be rediscovered. That is why the [[secret]] of the [[subject]]'s freedom lies in revealing the [[meaning]] of this social [[essence]], of rediscovering its laws and restoring harmony and [[transparency]] to social relations. The anarchist Kropotkin (1947, p 45) believed that there was a [[natural]] sociability to be found among both animals and [[humans]], upon which free cooperation and [[ethical]] [[action]] could be established. Therefore, [[The Subject|the subject]]'s [[struggle]] for freedom is determined by the dialectical unfolding of this rational truth, and the overcoming of the [[external]] limitations of political power and authority. Once centralized political authority is destroyed, social relations will become [[transparent]] - hence, Bakunin's positivistic [[faith]] in the ability of [[science]] to perceive the fundamental workings of society, and his [[belief]] that the anarchist revolution would be a [[scientific]] revolution (Bakunin, 1953, p 76). Thus, the anarchist revolution would involve a [[destruction]] of political authority, but in this destruction there was, at the same time, the restoration of a rational social order. In other words, the anarchist transgression of authority is inseparable from a "[[return]]" to a lost social fullness.
"What you [[want]] is [[another]] master!": Lacan's dystopia
[[Psychoanalytic Theory|Psychoanalytic theory ]] has a less sanguine and utopian view of human [[nature]] and the possibilities of social harmony. [[Freud]] saw the human [[instinct]] as [[naturally]] [[aggressive]] and destructive rather than cooperative, and he was somewhat skeptical about the utopian claims of revolutionary politics. 1 This skepticism was also shared by Lacan, and was most notoriously demonstrated in his address to [[university]] students in the May [[1968]] uprising in [[Paris]]: "Revolutionary aspirations have only one possibility: always to end up in the discourse of the master. [[Experience]] has proven this. What you aspire to as revolutionaries is a master. You will have one!" (Lacan in Stavrakakis, 1999, p 12).
As unambiguous as this [[statement]] may seem, there are two implications that can be drawn from it in relation to the importance of psychoanalytic theory for radical politics. The first implication is a simple outright dismissal of any form of radical political [[activity]] - give up your [[hysterical]] revolutionary aspirations, as they will ultimately end in new forms of domination . This would seem to align Lacan with a [[conservative]] a-political stance, and put paid to the [[suggestion]] that there is anything in Lacanian theory that is of interest to radical politics. 2 However, it is possible to draw another implication here - one that, paradoxically, aligns Lacan with the anarchist position. One may suggest that this statement may be taken as a warning to radical politics about the dangers of reaffirming the structures of power and authority as a consequence of a revolution. Was this not precisely the same warning that the anarchists gave to Marxists regarding the question of the State and political institutions? In this [[sense]], then, both the anarchist and Lacanian positions point to the place of power - that is, the dangers of power and authority being reproduced in one's very attempt to overcome [[them]]. Both perspectives address, in other words, the position of the revolutionary vis-à-vis the place of domination he contests - the revolutionary must confront the hidden, disavowed authoritarian implications of his own endeavor. In other words, the revolutionary is asked, is the authority you contest not already immanent in your position as revolutionary, and will your revolution not lead to a perpetuation of this authority? So the question to be addressed here is: how can radical politics be reconfigured in such a way that it can avoid the reaffirmation of power and authority? This was the anarchist question - to some degree it is also the Lacanian question.
Part of this reconfiguring of radical politics via Lacanian theory would, however, involve a critique of the [[conceptual]] structures of anarchism itself. Since anarchism, like Marxism, is a discourse of revolution, it must be submitted to a Lacanian critique of the revolutionary position and its immanent [[authoritarianism]]. In other words, does anarchism itself reaffirm the authority it transgresses?; in seeking to overcome the position of the master, will it install a new master in its place? That is to say, is anarchism also caught up in the authoritarian discourse of the master - the very discourse it ostensibly seeks to abolish? It would seem that from a Lacanian perspective, there is a structural link between the position of the revolutionist and the position of the master - one implying the other. It is precisely this hidden connection between revolutionary [[desire]] and the domination it contests, between transgression and authority, that is the central problem of revolutionary politics.
In exploring this connection between revolutionary transgression and authority, we must turn to Lacan's reformulation of [[Hegel]]'s [[Master/Slave Dialectic|master/slave dialectic]]. Indeed, in the paradoxical relationship between master and slave, there is reflected the central problem in anarchism - the ambiguous and hidden connection between revolutionary desire and authority. In Hegel's dialectic, [[desire,]] which is really the desire of the self, is only realized through the desire of the other. In other words, what is desired is the [[recognition]] by the other of one's own desire. This self-recognition therefore involves the [[negation]] of the other's self-recognition - as there can be only room for one - thus instigating a relationship of domination between the one who recognizes and desires the other (the slave) and the one who is recognized and desired (the master). However, because self-recognition is based on recognition by the [[other, the]] [[identity]] of the master - the one who is recognized - is dependent on the identity of the slave - the one who recognizes. This introduces into the relationship a paradoxical ambiguity and potential [[reversal]] of positions. We can see this precariousness in all relationships of political and social domination - the authority of the lord is always dependent on the recognition of this authority by the bondsman; without this it would collapse. This opposition is only reconciled, according to Hegel, in the [[universal]] and homogeneous State - wherein both the master and slave recognize themselves in each other.
However, it is precisely this reconciliation that Lacan rejects, suggesting that even in this universal State there would still be divisions wrought by rivalries between egos - a mutual [[envy]], for [[instance]], between "scientists" and non-scientists, particularly over the status of [[knowledge]] (Borch-Jacobsen, 1991, p 90). This was precisely the same [[contradiction]] that anarchists pointed to in the [[concept]] of the Marxist workers' State, which was supposed to be the institution wherein class divisions would be reconciled. On the contrary, Bakunin (1973, p 266) predicted that new class divisions would emerge - those between a bureaucratic class of scientists and experts, and the rest of the population. However, there is an important [[difference]] here: what the anarchists reject is the [[idea]] that dialectical reconciliation can be achieved through the State, while Lacan rejects the idea of dialectical reconciliation altogether.
In other words, what a political revolution succeeds in doing is merely to re-instantiate itself within the structure of the master's discourse. It merely completes the circle, once again ending up in the master's discourse - the very position of authority that it tried to negate. It is here that Lacan seems to reflect the anarchist argument about the "place of power" or the structural imperative of authority to perpetuate itself, even in revolutionary situations. In other words, both the anarchists and Lacan would see power and authority in terms of a specific structural [[logic]] of self-perpetuation, pointing to the dangers of revolutionary endeavors that do not deal directly with this question. This would apply particularly to Marxism, which ends up in a 'changing of the guard'. As anarchists showed, Marxism falls into the trap of the place of power because it thinks it can transform society without transforming the structure of authority; because it seeks merely to put another [[agent]] in the position of authority - the worker in place of the bourgeois. "And this is why," as Lacan says "all he has done is change masters" (Grigg, Seminar XVII, Ch 2, p 6).
Given this intractability of authority, how is it possible to [[affect]] social change without merely reaffirming it? How is it possible, in other words, to escape the master? The only way to undermine the master, for Lacan, is through the [[discourse of the analyst]]. However, this [[process]] can only begin once the intermediary [[Discourse of the Hysteric|discourse of the hysteric ]] is passed through. According to Bracher, because of the dominance of the S1 in the master discourse, there is produced an [[excess]] of [[enjoyment]] - the a or plus-de-jour - for which there is no place in this discourse, and which is therefore excluded and projected onto the slave (Bracher, 1993, p 64). Therefore, the knowledge of the [[object]] [[cause]] of the master's own desire is denied to him. What this means is, however, that the position of the master is really the position of [[castration]] - as he is cut off from his [[object a]] , from enjoyment. What the master discourse conceals, then, behind its posture of certainty and fullness of identity, is a fundamental lack.
Now it is precisely this lack that the discourse of the hysteric, in a paradoxical fashion, hones in on. The position of the hysteric is characterized by an [[identification]] with an [[unsatisfied]] desire. As the agent here realizes her lack - the lack of the [[object of desire]] that will complete her identity - her position is characterized by a [[demand]] to [[know]] who she is and what her desire is (Verhaeghe, 2001, p 28). This demand is always addressed to the other, and it is because of the nature of this demand that the hysteric makes a master out of the other. In other words, the hysteric's demand is addressed to the master, who is expected to provide an answer to the hysteric's desire. However, due to the impossibility of [[satisfying]] this desire, the answer that the master provides is always wrong or inadequate. In order to keep her desire alive, the hysteric therefore has a vested interest in sustaining the lack in the master. We can see, in this [[complex]] dialectic, the precise relation between these two discourses - the hysteric is always testing the knowledge and authority of the master who, in trying to conceal his lack and shore up his position of authority, provides answers that only expose his [[impotence]] and lack all the more.
Therefore, the hysteric questions, interrogates and resists the master but, at the same time, [[needs]] the master in order to sustain her insurrectionary desire. In political terms, then, we could say that while Marxism, despite its revolutionary aspirations, was ultimately part of the discourse of the master, anarchism would be part of the [[hysteric's discourse]]. This is because while Marxism, in its revolutionary endeavors, neglected the master's discourse - the place of power and authority - which was why it remained caught within it, anarchism, like the hysteric, focused on this place of authority itself, [[seeing]] it as the main impediment to the subject's freedom and fullness. So just as the hysteric sees the master as the cause of her [[alienation]], so the anarchist sees the State as the cause of the subject's alienation. However, despite - or more precisely through - its attempt to negate political authority, anarchism finds itself, paradoxically, reliant upon it in order to form its own revolutionary identity. I have shown the way, for instance, that in anarchist discourse the State functions as both an impediment to, and object cause of , revolutionary desire. So, in this analysis, just as the hysteric needs the master to have something to protest against, so the anarchist needs the State to constitute the subject's revolutionary identity.
[[Traversing]] the fantasy: the [[Discourse of the Analyst|discourse of the analyst]]
Despite this paradoxical relationship between the master and hysteric, there is still a [[real]] revolutionary potential in the Hysteric's discourse. However, in order to break out of the bind with the Master, another discourse must intervene - that of the analyst. According to Lacan, this discourse is the only real counterpoint to that of the master (Grigg, Seminar XVII, Ch 6, p 3) and the only way for the subject to escape it. So what happens here? Briefly, the [[role]] of analysis is to allow the subject to own his or her alienation and desire, by confronting him with his own [[Unconscious Fantasy|unconscious fantasy ]] - producing a gap between the subject and ego [[ideal]] - and to accept that the other, which supports this fantasy structure, is itself deficient, [[lacking]] and ungrounded (see Bracher, 1993, pp 68-73). This would be what Lacan calls la traversée du [[fantasme]] - crossing or [[traversing the fantasy]].
Let us try to understand this process in political terms - that is, in terms of the possibility of anarchism or, radical politics generally, escaping the master and traversing the political fantasy. We have seen that classical anarchism, as a radical political philosophy, is sustained not only by the idea of a rational social "object" that determines the revolutionary process but also by the utopian idea of society on the "other side" of power - a society, in other words, without the distortions and dislocations wrought by power and authority. That is to say, there is a utopian fantasy of an Edenic state of fullness and reconciliation that would prevail in society once power relations have been eliminated. Furthermore, there is, in anarchism, an [[idealization]] of the subject - the subject is seen as embodying an inherent [[morality]] and [[rationality]], the full expression of which has been distorted by political authority. In other words, there is a political fantasy that sustains the revolutionary desire at the heart of anarchism - this fantasy consists of a Manichean [[division]] between the subject and authority, and the promise of a return to a lost rational and moral social objectivity once this authority has been eliminated.
The problem with this discourse, however, is the essentialist and positivistic assumptions that it relies upon, assumptions that are no longer sustainable. For anarchism to become more relevant to contemporary radical politics and theory, it would have to abandon these assumptions, and in particular the utopian fantasy - the [[Object A|object a ]] - around which its revolutionary desire is [[structured]]. Moreover, anarchism must confront what is so disturbing to its own idealizations - that is, the desire for power at the heart of human subjectivity. This desire for power is something that is both acknowledged, yet disavowed, in classical anarchism. For instance, Bakunin talks about the power [[principle]]: "Every man carries within himself the germs of the lust for power, and every germ, as we know, because of a basic law of life, necessarily must develop and grow." (Bakunin, 1953, p 248). Perhaps we can say that this "power principle" is the [[traumatic]] unconscious fantasy of classical anarchism - something that disturbs its idealization of the essentially moral and rational subject. So what anarchism needs to do is confront this traumatic realization - to accept that, at the heart of the human subject there is not a [[latent]] moral and rational essence, but rather a desire or [[drive]] for power. Moreover, this would also involve the acknowledgment that power will always be [[present]] to a degree in every political [[symbolization]] - even those based on the utopian ideal of a society free from power. The process of political symbolization will always involve an [[exclusion]] of a particular element - and this, of course, is the operation of power.
The contingency of the political
But what does this mean for anarchism and emancipative politics generally? Simply, that it must abandon the fantasy of utopian fullness and recognize that the other is lacking, that there is no natural or essential commonality that holds society together. In other words, what radical politics must acknowledge and, indeed, affirm is that there is no [[dialectical process]] or underlying social logic that determines the political - that the political is always radically ungrounded, indeterminate and [[contingent]] . Stavrakakis here talks about the crisis of the utopian project, suggesting that instead "the politics of today is the politics of aporia." (Stavrakakis, 1999, p 99) Utopian political projects, including anarchism, were based on the fantasy of a society without dislocation and [[antagonism]], and were attempts to conceal or "patch up" the very lack in the social itself - the lack that was irreducible and indeed, constitutive of the political itself .
[[Traversing the Fantasy|Traversing the fantasy ]] in the political sense, then, would mean recognizing this irreducible [[void]] in the social - the void that jeopardizes and dislocates any political symbolization. It would mean acknowledging the contingency and undecidability of politics, and that transformative and emancipative political projects can never hope to transform the whole of society - there will always be something that eludes them. Society, in other words, is an impossible object that can never be grasped in this way. Indeed, as Stavrakakis argues, Lacanian political theory is based around a fundamental impossibility or lack: "Lacanian political theory aims at bringing to the fore, again and again, the [[lack in the Other]], the same lack that utopian fantasy attempts to mask..." (Stavrakakis, 1999, p 166). This would mean, moreover, that any kind of radical political critique of institutions and social practices could not be from the perspective of some sort of essentialist subjectivity or social order that institutions are seen to impose themselves upon, but rather would operate within the discursive limits of the institution itself - according to the Lacanian realization that all social practices, even revolutionary ones, are part of, and indeed dependent upon, institutional and discursive structures themselves (Copjec, 1990, p 51).
Politics of the [[event]]
Rancière is a thinker for whom the contingent and disruptive element of the politics is central. This disruptive element is based on a constitutive incommensurability or "disagreement" ( mésentente ) between the demos and the "police" order, an incommensurability that Rancière traces back to its origins in Athenian democracy. The demos, or "the [[people]]", is defined by its exclusion from the polis - it is the formless mass that has "no part" in the political life of the city and, as such, has been the [[victim]] of a fundamental "wrong" that must be redressed. The "police" order refers to the status quo , the dominant social and political structures. This order is based on a process of "calculation" that seeks to [[separate]] the [[individual]] from the mass and assign each to his place within the dominant order. Its tendency is therefore towards a de-[[politicization]] of the mass, and a reduction of the political terrain through a process of individualization. However, this incommensurability gives rise to disputes in which fundamental political questions are raised: "It produces both new inscriptions of equality within liberty and a fresh sphere of visibility for further demonstrations" (Rancière, 1999, p 42). So for Rancière, there are moments of rupture in which identities become indeterminate, and in which dominant social hierarchies and structures are momentarily dislocated or suspended, allowing new and unpredictable political [[meanings]] to be articulated. This would be similar to the transitional spaces between discourses that I have referred to, in which new political meanings - even revolutionary ones - may intervene. The key point here, however, is that there is no utopian [[goal]] for politics - or at least there is not one that can ever be reached; rather politics must be seen as a series of clashes or "disagreements" in which its inherently unstable and contingent nature is brought to the fore.
[[Slavoj zizek|Slavoj Zizek ]] also sees politics in terms of a fundamental moment of rupture - an event that breaks with accepted political identities and [[categories]], and allows new meanings to be produced. In a number of [[texts]], Zizek has invoked a sort of revolutionary Act that fundamentally breaks [[The Deadlock|the deadlock ]] of the contemporary politico-[[ideological]] paradigms of liberal [[multiculturalism]] and capitalist globalization: "Today, more than ever, one has to insist that the only way to open the emergence of an Event is that of breaking the [[vicious cycle]] of globalization-with-particularization by (re)asserting the dimension of [[Universality]] against capitalist globalization." (Zizek, 1999, p 211) This would be, in Lacanian terms, a kind of passage à l'[[acte]] - an ethical decision - that transgresses the dominant [[symbolic]] coordinates of society.
However, the political event, if theorized in this way, is fundamentally ambiguous. On the one hand, the ethical decision can refer to a kind of leap into an abyss of contingency and freedom, in which there is an impossible gap between the subject and the pre-established [[normative]] criteria that are supposed to [[guide]] his action. According to [[Ernesto Laclau]], for instance, this unstable relationship between the ethical and the normative is the basis for a hegemonic politics, in which there is always a gap between the universal and particular, between the empty place of the universal and the particular identity that attempts, ultimately unsuccessfully, to embody it (Butler et al , 2000, p 81). This politics of hegemony - or politics of the lack - implies a democratic and emancipative contingency, in which the political field is constituted through its [[openness]] to different identities and forms of engagement. For Zizek, on the other hand, however, the politico-ethical decision seems to imply a form of authoritarian or 'terrorist' politics, which at [[times]] he openly advocates: "The only 'realistic' prospect is to ground a new political universality by opting for the impossible, fully assuming the place of the exception, with no taboos, no apriori norms ('[[human rights]]', 'democracy'), respect for which would prevent us also from resignifying [[terror]], the ruthless exercise of power, the spirit of sacrifice... (Butler et al , 2000, p 326)"
An-archism and radical politics today
So it would appear that the event that can intervene in the transitional spaces between discourses is always potentially dangerous, and that this would only seem to confirm Lacan's original warning about radical politics - that it will inevitably end up invoking a new master. However, one could suggest here that rather than succumbing to the temptation to [[pass]] to [[The Act|the act ]] , immediately seeking to reinscribe the political event within the discourse of the master as a way of stabilizing the revolution, perhaps instead one could remain faithful to its constitutive openness and its radically contingent possibilities. This would imply a radical political ethics of suspension and indeterminacy that refuses to be grounded in a concrete [[ontological]] order. Indeed, we might refer here to an an-archic politico-ethical position, one that distinguishes itself from classical anarchism by rejecting the ontological ground, essentialist identities and utopian structures that it is founded upon. Schurmann (1987, p 10) characterizes an-anarchic action as action without a "why?" - that is, action that is not grounded in absolute rationalist principles. In a similar way, we might characterize Lacanian an-anarchic action as action without a master - in other words, action that no longer invokes the master, instead remaining open to the indeterminacy of the political situation.
As a concrete example of a Lacanian an-anarchic politics in this sense, we could point to what is broadly termed the "anti-globalization" movement - a protest movement that has exploded across our political horizons in recent years, from Seattle to Cancun. This is a series of struggles against the neo-liberal capitalist [[vision]] of globalization that so dominates us today. What is radical about this movement is not only the breadth of its political agenda but also the new forms of political action that it entails. It is fundamentally different from both the identity politics that has recently prevailed in Western liberal societies, as well as from the Marxist politics of [[class struggle]]. On the one hand, the [[anti-globalization movement]] unites different identities around a common struggle; and yet this common ground is not determined in advance, or based on the priority of particular class interests, but rather is articulated in a contingent way during the struggle itself. Having moved beyond the [[cultural]] and [[sexual]] identity wars of the 1980s and 1990s - the PC litany of victimizations that passed as "subversive" politics - radical politics today has once again placed [[capitalism]] back on the agenda, only not in the same way as Marxism did. It now targets new sites of oppression and domination within the capitalist system: corporate power and greed, G-M products, workplace surveillance, environmental degradation, and so on.
Moreover, what makes this movement radical is its unpredictability and indeterminacy - the way that unexpected [[links]] and alliances are formed between different identities and groups that would otherwise have little in common. So while this movement is universal, in the sense that it invokes a common emancipative horizon that interpellates the identities of participants, it also rejects the [[false]] universality of Marxist struggles that deny difference and subordinate other struggles to the central role of the [[proletariat]] - or, to be more precise, to the vanguard role of the party. It is perhaps not surprising, then, that anarchist groups feature prominently in these protests. It may be seen as an anarchistic form of politics because it rejects centralism and hierarchy, preferring structures that are more democratic and pluralistic. 5 Moreover, it remains open to a [[plurality]] of different identities and struggles. Just as classical anarchists insisted, in opposition to [[Marx]], that the revolutionary struggle should not be confined or determined by the class interests of the industrial proletariat, and must also be open to peasants, the [[lumpenproletariat]], and intellectuals déclassé , etc., so too the contemporary anti-globalization movement includes a broad range of struggles, identities and interests - trade unions, students, environmentalists, indigenous groups, ethnic minorities, peace activists, and so on.
What this amounts to, then, is a heterogeneous series of struggles that, although "quilted" around a general politics of resistance to capitalism, does not have a definite [[master signifier]]. Or, perhaps it may be more precise to say that the [[Master Signifier|master signifier ]] here is empty or lacking in [[content]]. Paradoxically, what holds the movement together is a [[rejection]] of [[transcendental]] identities, or in this case, [[logos]]. For instance, Naomi [[Klein]], in her exploration of global corporate capitalism and resistance to it, shows the way in which logos have become the universal [[signifiers]] of corporate cultural domination: "Logos, by the force of ubiquity, have become the closest [[thing]] we have to an international language, recognized and understood in many more places than [[English]]" (Klein, 2001, p xxi). The predominance of corporate logos or brands indicates, according to Klein, a fundamental shift in the dynamics of capitalism, from the selling of products to the marketing of "lifestyles" - for instance, the Nike swoosh evoking ideas of sportsmanship and athleticism (Klein, 2001, p 56) - thus creating a series of signifiers that we are expected to conform to, and through which we come to understand ourselves. In this sense also, the logo can be understood in Lacanian terms as a master signifier - that which provides the consumer with a certain identity. 6
The title of Klein's book implies precisely a rejection, or at least a [[subversion]] of logos as signifiers of corporate power. She examines a number of different strategies of resistance to the corporate culture of branding, from "culture jamming", or the parodying of logos and advertisements, to more concrete forms of activism such as Reclaim The Streets campaigns. However, this very rejection of logos or master signifiers - No Logo - becomes in itself an "[[empty signifier]]", a stand in that "sutures" together in a contingent way the diverse field of struggles. 7 As [[Miller]] (1977/8, pp 26-28) argues, "suturing" describes a process by which the subject is joined into the signifying [[chain]], allowing the signifier to stand in for the subject's [[absence]] in discourse. In the same way, different political identities and struggles against different aspects of capitalist globalization can be joined together in a [[signifying chain]] through a signifier without a [[signified]] - a logo without a brand, thus implying the very rejection of brands. Therefore, it is not correct to say that No Logo operates in the same way as a logo or master signifier - rather, it is a signifier emptied of content, and it is precisely through this emptiness that it can [[represent]] the [[heterogeneity]] of political struggles around capitalist globalization.
1. Stavrakakis recalls Freud's 'half-conversion' to Bolshevism: "when he was told that [[communism]] would bring at first some hard years and then harmony and [[happiness]], he answered that he believed in the first half of this programme." (Stavrakakis, 1999, p 12).
2. Indeed, Lacan refers dismissively to the "libertarian hook" that supposedly attaches itself to psychoanalysis, pointing to certain attempts to see psychoanalysis as a practice that can free us from the Law (see Grigg, Seminar XVII, Ch 8, p 2).
3. Here I will be relying on Russell Grigg's unpublished draft [[translation]] of [[The Seminar]] of [[Jacques lacan|Jacques Lacan]]. Book 17: The Other Side of Psychoanalysis 1969-1970. References from this seminar will henceforth be cited in the text under Grigg. ( * Note - the pages in this draft copy do not run consecutively from chapter to chapter).4. Moreover, it is the role of the [[University discourse|University Discourse ]] to provide the justification through knowledge, of the discursive "truth" of the Master's position.
5. See Graeber's (2002) [[discussion]] of some of these anarchistic structures and forms of organization in "The New Anarchists".
6. Indeed Lacan himself links advertising and consumer products to the discourse of the master: "We are becoming increasingly familiar with the functions of an agent. We live at a time at which we know what this conveys - fake stuff, advertising stuff, which has to be sold. But we also know that it works with that, at the point we have come to in the expansion, the paroxysm, of the discourse of the master in a society that is founded on it" (Grigg, Seminar XVII, Chapter 8, p 13).
Biography: About the author
Saul Newman is a postdoctoral fellow and lecturer at the University of Western Australia. His research is in the area of contemporary political theory and [[continental philosophy]], with particular focus on the themes of power, [[ideology]], radical politics, hegemony, [[Psychoanalysis and Post-Marxism|psychoanalysis and post-Marxism]]. He is the author of From Bakunin to Lacan: Anti-authoritarianism and the Dislocation of Power (2001).
[Author Affiliation]
1 University of Western Australia, Crawley, Australia
Correspondence: Dr Saul Newman, Department of [[Political science|Political Science]], University of Western Australia, 35 Stirling Highway, CRAWLEY WA 6009, Australia. E-mail: snewman@cyllene.uwa.edu.au
[[Category:Religion]]
[[Category:Politics]]
Anonymous user

Navigation menu