Difference between revisions of "Saussure's Concept of the Sign"

From No Subject - Encyclopedia of Psychoanalysis
Jump to: navigation, search
 
(The LinkTitles extension automatically added links to existing pages (<a rel="nofollow" class="external free" href="https://github.com/bovender/LinkTitles">https://github.com/bovender/LinkTitles</a>).)
(Tags: Mobile edit, Mobile web edit)
 
Line 2: Line 2:
 
<br>
 
<br>
  
</font><blockquote><blockquote><font size="+1">[Saussure introduces the structuralist point of view into
+
</font><blockquote><blockquote><font size="+1">[[[Saussure]] introduces the [[structuralist]] point of view into
linguistics which is marked first of all by giving special relief to
+
[[linguistics]] which is marked first of all by giving special relief to
the synchronic dimension in the study of language.  The
+
the [[synchronic]] [[dimension]] in the study of [[language]].  The
synchronic dimension is distinguished from the diachronic, that
+
synchronic dimension is distinguished from the [[diachronic]], that
is, historic.  The idea is that an account of the present meaning
+
is, historic.  The [[idea]] is that an account of the [[present]] [[meaning]]
of words and sentences, i.e. semantics,  can't be reduced to a
+
of [[words]] and sentences, i.e. semantics,  can't be reduced to a
 
historical study.  This may seem obvious to us, but the study of
 
historical study.  This may seem obvious to us, but the study of
linguistic meaning prior to Saussure had been historical with
+
[[linguistic]] meaning prior to Saussure had been historical with
considerations of structure limited largely to a consideration of
+
considerations of [[structure]] limited largely to a consideration of
grammar.  The idea is that meaning, or signification, depends on
+
grammar.  The idea is that meaning, or [[signification]], depends on
the SYSTEM of language given by a number of laws of equilibrium
+
the SYSTEM of language given by a [[number]] of laws of equilibrium
which constitute the relative systemic stability of linguistic
+
which constitute the relative systemic [[stability]] of linguistic
meaning at the moment when, in virtue of this system, one
+
meaning at the [[moment]] when, in virtue of this [[system]], one
speaks.  So we have the distinction between <i>la langue</i>  and <i> la
+
speaks.  So we have the [[distinction]] between <i>la [[langue]]</i>  and <i> la
parole.</i>  Language is the articulated use of the system, <i>la langue</i>
+
[[parole]].</i>  Language is the articulated use of the system, <i>la langue</i>
  
in speech, <i>la parole.  </i>La langue is language minus la parole.  It is
+
in [[speech]], <i>la parole.  </i>La langue is language minus la parole.  It is
difficult to overestimate the significance of Saussure's idea for
+
difficult to overestimate the [[significance]] of Saussure's idea for
a whole generation of French thinkers.  For insofar as language
+
a [[whole]] generation of [[French]] thinkers.  For insofar as language
enters into the determination of a whole variety of social
+
enters into the determination of a whole variety of [[social]]
 
phenomena, its effects as structure enter in as well.  Post
 
phenomena, its effects as structure enter in as well.  Post
 
structuralist thinkers remain in debt to Saussure for however
 
structuralist thinkers remain in debt to Saussure for however
dynamic and open-textured
+
[[dynamic]] and open-textured
structures come to be, one
+
[[structures]] come to be, one
 
can't go back to purely
 
can't go back to purely
 
historical modes of
 
historical modes of
interpretation.  The
+
[[interpretation]].  The
structuring effects of
+
[[structuring]] effects of
discourse, the agency of the
+
[[discourse]], the [[agency]] of the
letter in Lacan's terms, must be taken into account.]</font></blockquote><p><font size="+1"><br>
+
[[letter]] in [[Lacan]]'s [[terms]], must be taken into account.]</font></blockquote><p><font size="+1"><br>
 
<br>
 
<br>
  
  
  
</font></p><blockquote><font size="+1">1. <i>Sign, Signified, Signifier</i><br><br>
+
</font></p><blockquote><font size="+1">1. <i>[[Sign]], [[Signified]], [[Signifier]]</i><br><br>
  
 
     Some people regard language, when reduced to its elements, as<br>
 
     Some people regard language, when reduced to its elements, as<br>
a naming-process only‹a list of words, each corresponding to the<br>
+
a naming-[[process]] only‹a [[list]] of words, each corresponding to the<br>
  
thing that it names. For example:</font><p>
+
[[thing]] that it names. For example:</font><p>
 
<font size="+1"><br>
 
<font size="+1"><br>
 
<br>
 
<br>
Line 52: Line 52:
 
<br>
 
<br>
 
     This conception is open to criticism at several points. It assumes<br>
 
     This conception is open to criticism at several points. It assumes<br>
that ready-made ideas exist before words (on this point, see below,<br>
+
that ready-made [[ideas]] [[exist]] before words (on this point, see below,<br>
p. 111); it does not tell us whether a name is vocal or psychological<br>
+
p. 111); it does not tell us whether a [[name]] is vocal or [[psychological]]<br>
  
in nature (<i>arbor</i>, for instance, can be considered from either view-<br>
+
in [[nature]] (<i>arbor</i>, for [[instance]], can be considered from either view-<br>
 
point); finally, it lets us assume that the linking of a name and a<br>
 
point); finally, it lets us assume that the linking of a name and a<br>
 
thing is a very simple operation‹an assumption that is anything<br>
 
thing is a very simple operation‹an assumption that is anything<br>
but true. But this rather naive approach can bring us near the<br>
+
but [[true]]. But this rather naive approach can bring us near the<br>
truth by showing us that the linguistic unit is a double entity, one<br>
+
[[truth]] by showing us that the linguistic unit is a [[double]] entity, one<br>
 
formed by the associating of two terms<br><br>
 
formed by the associating of two terms<br><br>
  
Line 69: Line 69:
  
 
     The linguistic sign unites, not a thing and a name, but a concept<br>
 
     The linguistic sign unites, not a thing and a name, but a concept<br>
and a sound-image.[l] The latter is not the material sound, a purely<br>
+
and a sound-[[image]].[l] The latter is not the [[material]] sound, a purely<br>
physical thing, but the psychological imprint of the sound, the<br>
+
[[physical]] thing, but the psychological imprint of the sound, the<br>
 
impression that it makes on our senses. The sound-image is sensory,<br>
 
impression that it makes on our senses. The sound-image is sensory,<br>
and if I happen to call it "material,"' it is only in that sense, and by<br>
+
and if I happen to call it "material,"' it is only in that [[sense]], and by<br>
way of opposing it to the other term of the association, the concept,<br>
+
way of opposing it to the [[other]] term of the [[association]], the [[concept]],<br>
  
 
which is generally more abstract.<br><br>
 
which is generally more abstract.<br><br>
Line 80: Line 80:
 
parent when we observe our own speech. Without moving our lips<br>
 
parent when we observe our own speech. Without moving our lips<br>
 
or tongue, we can talk to ourselves or recite mentally a selection of<br>
 
or tongue, we can talk to ourselves or recite mentally a selection of<br>
verse. Because we regard the words of our language as sound-<br>
+
verse. Because we [[regard]] the words of our language as sound-<br>
images, we must avoid speaking of the "phonemes" that make up<br>
+
[[images]], we must avoid [[speaking]] of the "phonemes" that make up<br>
the words. This term, which suggests vocal activity, is applicable<br>
+
the words. This term, which suggests vocal [[activity]], is applicable<br>
to the spoken word only, to the realization of the inner image in<br>
+
to the spoken [[word]] only, to the realization of the inner image in<br>
  
 
discourse. We can avoid that misunderstanding by speaking of the<br>
 
discourse. We can avoid that misunderstanding by speaking of the<br>
<i>sounds </i>and <i>syllables</i> of a word provided we remember that the<br>
+
<i>sounds </i>and <i>syllables</i> of a word provided we [[remember]] that the<br>
 
names refer to the sound-image.<br><br>
 
names refer to the sound-image.<br><br>
  
Line 96: Line 96:
  
 
     The two elements are intimately united, and each recalls the<br>
 
     The two elements are intimately united, and each recalls the<br>
other. Whether we try to find the meaning of the Latin word <i>arbor</i><br>
+
other. Whether we try to find the meaning of the [[Latin]] word <i>arbor</i><br>
 
or the word that Latin uses to designate the concept "tree," it is</font></p><p>
 
or the word that Latin uses to designate the concept "tree," it is</font></p><p>
 
<font size="+1"><br>
 
<font size="+1"><br>
 
<br>
 
<br>
 
<font size="-1">1. The term sound-image may seem to be too restricted inasmuch as beside<br>
 
<font size="-1">1. The term sound-image may seem to be too restricted inasmuch as beside<br>
the representation of the sounds of a word there is also that of its articulation,<br>
+
the [[representation]] of the sounds of a word there is also that of its articulation,<br>
  
 
tbe muscular image of the phonational act. But for F. de Saussure language is<br>
 
tbe muscular image of the phonational act. But for F. de Saussure language is<br>
 
essentially a depository, a thing received from without (see p. 13). The sound<br>
 
essentially a depository, a thing received from without (see p. 13). The sound<br>
image is par excellence the natural representation of the word as a fact of<br>
+
image is par excellence the [[natural]] representation of the word as a fact of<br>
potential language, outside any actual use of it in speaking. The motor side is<br>
+
potential language, [[outside]] any actual use of it in speaking. The motor side is<br>
thus implied or, in any event, occupies only a subordinate role with respect<br>
+
thus implied or, in any [[event]], occupies only a subordinate [[role]] with respect<br>
 
to the sound-image. [Ed.]</font></font></p><p>
 
to the sound-image. [Ed.]</font></font></p><p>
 
<font size="+1"><br>
 
<font size="+1"><br>
Line 118: Line 118:
 
<br>
 
<br>
 
<br>
 
<br>
clear that only the associations sanctioned by that language appeal<br>
+
clear that only the [[associations]] sanctioned by that language appeal<br>
to us to conform to reality, and we disregard whatever others<br>
+
to us to conform to [[reality]], and we disregard whatever [[others]]<br>
 
might be imagined.<br><br>
 
might be imagined.<br><br>
  
Line 139: Line 139:
 
<br>
 
<br>
 
     Ambiguity would disappear if the three notions involved here<br>
 
     Ambiguity would disappear if the three notions involved here<br>
were designated by three names, each suggesting and opposing the<br>
+
were designated by [[three]] names, each suggesting and opposing the<br>
others. I propose to retain the word <i>sign [signe] </i>to designate the<br>
+
others. I propose to retain the word <i>sign [[[signe]]] </i>to designate the<br>
 
whole and to replace <i>concept</i> and <i>sound-image</i> respectively by<br>
 
whole and to replace <i>concept</i> and <i>sound-image</i> respectively by<br>
  
Line 146: Line 146:
 
[signifié]</i> and
 
[signifié]</i> and
 
<i>signifier
 
<i>signifier
[signifiant]</i>;
+
[[[signifiant]]]</i>;
 
the last two
 
the last two
 
terms have<br>
 
terms have<br>
the advantage of indicating the opposition that separates them<br>
+
the advantage of indicating the opposition that separates [[them]]<br>
 
from each other and from the whole of which they are parts.  As<br>
 
from each other and from the whole of which they are parts.  As<br>
regards <i>sign</i>, if I am satisfied with it, this is simply because I do not<br>
+
regards <i>sign</i>, if I am [[satisfied]] with it, this is simply because I do not<br>
know of any word to replace it, the ordinary language suggesting<br>
+
[[know]] of any word to replace it, the ordinary language suggesting<br>
 
no other.<br><br>
 
no other.<br><br>
  
Line 159: Line 159:
 
any study of this type.</font></p><p><font size="+1"><br>
 
any study of this type.</font></p><p><font size="+1"><br>
  
<i>2. Principle 1: The Arbitrary Nature of the Sign</i><br><br>
+
<i>2. [[Principle]] 1: The [[Arbitrary]] Nature of the Sign</i><br><br>
  
 
     The bond between the signifier and the signified is arbitrary.<br>
 
     The bond between the signifier and the signified is arbitrary.<br>
Line 170: Line 170:
 
the succession of sounds <i>s-ö-r</i> which serves as its signifier in French;<br>
 
the succession of sounds <i>s-ö-r</i> which serves as its signifier in French;<br>
 
that it could be represented equally by just any other sequence is<br>
 
that it could be represented equally by just any other sequence is<br>
proved by differences among languages and by the very existence<br>
+
proved by differences among [[languages]] and by the very [[existence]]<br>
  
 
of different languages: the signified "ox" has as its signifier <i>b-ô-f</i><br>
 
of different languages: the signified "ox" has as its signifier <i>b-ô-f</i><br>
Line 177: Line 177:
 
     No one disputes the principle of the arbitrary nature of the sign,<br>
 
     No one disputes the principle of the arbitrary nature of the sign,<br>
 
but it is often easier to discover a truth than to assign to it its<br>
 
but it is often easier to discover a truth than to assign to it its<br>
proper place. Principle I dominates all the linguistics of language;<br>
+
proper [[place]]. Principle I dominates all the linguistics of language;<br>
 
its consequences are numberless. It is true that not all of them are<br>
 
its consequences are numberless. It is true that not all of them are<br>
  
Line 185: Line 185:
  
 
     One remark in passing: when semiology becomes organized as<br>
 
     One remark in passing: when semiology becomes organized as<br>
a science, the question will arise whether or not it properly includes<br>
+
a [[science]], the question will arise whether or not it properly includes<br>
modes of expression based on completely natural signs, such as<br>
+
modes of expression based on completely natural [[signs]], such as<br>
 
pantomime. Supposing that the new science welcomes them, its<br>
 
pantomime. Supposing that the new science welcomes them, its<br>
 
main concern will still be the whole group of systems grounded on<br>
 
main concern will still be the whole group of systems grounded on<br>
  
 
the arbitrariness of the sign. In fact, every means of expression used<br>
 
the arbitrariness of the sign. In fact, every means of expression used<br>
in society is based, in principle, on collective behavior or‹what<br>
+
in [[society]] is based, in principle, on collective [[behavior]] or‹what<br>
amounts to the same thing‹on convention. Polite formulas, for<br>
+
amounts to the same thing‹on convention. Polite [[formulas]], for<br>
 
instance, though often imbued with a certain natural expressive-<br>
 
instance, though often imbued with a certain natural expressive-<br>
ness (as in the case of a Chinese who greets his emperor by bowing<br>
+
ness (as in the [[case]] of a Chinese who greets his emperor by bowing<br>
down to the ground nine times), are nonetheless fixed by rule; it is<br>
+
down to the ground nine [[times]]), are nonetheless fixed by rule; it is<br>
this rule and not the intrinsic value of the gestures that obliges one<br>
+
this rule and not the intrinsic [[value]] of the gestures that obliges one<br>
 
to use them. Signs that are wholly arbitrary realize better than the<br>
 
to use them. Signs that are wholly arbitrary realize better than the<br>
others the ideal of the semiological process; that is why language,<br>
+
others the [[ideal]] of the semiological process; that is why language,<br>
  
the most complex and universal of all systems of expression, is also<br>
+
the most [[complex]] and [[universal]] of all systems of expression, is also<br>
 
the most characteristic; in this sense linguistics can become the<br>
 
the most characteristic; in this sense linguistics can become the<br>
master-pattern for all branches of semiology although language is<br>
+
[[master]]-pattern for all branches of [[semiology]] although language is<br>
only one particular semiological system.<br><br>
+
only one [[particular]] semiological system.<br><br>
  
 
     The word <i>symbol</i> has been used to designate the linguistic sign,<br>
 
     The word <i>symbol</i> has been used to designate the linguistic sign,<br>
Line 209: Line 209:
  
 
particular weighs against the use of this term. One characteristic<br>
 
particular weighs against the use of this term. One characteristic<br>
of the symbol is that it is never wholly arbitrary; it is not empty,<br>
+
of the [[symbol]] is that it is never wholly arbitrary; it is not empty,<br>
 
for there is the rudiment of a natural bond between the signifier<br>
 
for there is the rudiment of a natural bond between the signifier<br>
 
and the signified. The symbol of justice, a pair of scales, could not<br>
 
and the signified. The symbol of justice, a pair of scales, could not<br>
Line 216: Line 216:
 
     The word <i>arbitrary</i> also calls ior commcnt. The term should not<br>
 
     The word <i>arbitrary</i> also calls ior commcnt. The term should not<br>
  
imply that the choice of the signifier is left entirely to the speaker<br>
+
imply that the [[choice]] of the signifier is [[left]] entirely to the [[speaker]]<br>
(we shall see below that the individual does not have the power to<br>
+
(we shall see below that the [[individual]] does not have the [[power]] to<br>
change a sign in any way once it has become established in the<br>
+
[[change]] a sign in any way once it has become established in the<br>
linguistic community); I mean that it is unmotivated, i.e. arbitrary<br>
+
linguistic [[community]]); I mean that it is unmotivated, i.e. arbitrary<br>
 
in that it actually has no natural connection with the signified.<br>
 
in that it actually has no natural connection with the signified.<br>
 
In concluding let us consider two objections that might be raised<br>
 
In concluding let us consider two objections that might be raised<br>
Line 226: Line 226:
 
     1) <i>Onomatopoeia</i> might be used to prove that the choice of the<br>
 
     1) <i>Onomatopoeia</i> might be used to prove that the choice of the<br>
  
signifier is not always arbitrary. But onomatopoeic formations are<br>
+
signifier is not always arbitrary. But onomatopoeic [[formations]] are<br>
never organic elements of a linguistic system. Besides, their number<br>
+
never [[organic]] elements of a linguistic system. Besides, their number<br>
 
is much smaller than is generally supposed. Words like French<br>
 
is much smaller than is generally supposed. Words like French<br>
 
<i>fouet</i> 'whip' or <i>glas</i> 'knell' may strike certain ears with suggestive<br>
 
<i>fouet</i> 'whip' or <i>glas</i> 'knell' may strike certain ears with suggestive<br>
 
sonority, but to see that they have not always had this property<br>
 
sonority, but to see that they have not always had this property<br>
we need only examine their Latin forms (<i>fouet</i> is derived from <i>fagus</i><br>
+
we [[need]] only examine their Latin forms (<i>fouet</i> is derived from <i>fagus</i><br>
  
 
'beech-tree,' <i>glas</i> from <i>classicum</i> 'sound of a trumpet'). The quality<br>
 
'beech-tree,' <i>glas</i> from <i>classicum</i> 'sound of a trumpet'). The quality<br>
Line 241: Line 241:
  
 
somewhat arbitrarily, for they are only approximate and more or<br>
 
somewhat arbitrarily, for they are only approximate and more or<br>
less conventional imitations of certain sounds (cf. English bo~boto<br>
+
less conventional imitations of certain sounds (cf. [[English]] bo~boto<br>
 
and French ouaoua). In addition, once these words have been intro-<br>
 
and French ouaoua). In addition, once these words have been intro-<br>
 
duced into the language, they are to a certain extent subjected to<br>
 
duced into the language, they are to a certain extent subjected to<br>
 
the same evolution‹phonetic, morphological, etc.‹that other<br>
 
the same evolution‹phonetic, morphological, etc.‹that other<br>
 
words undergo (cf. <i>pigeon</i>, ultimately from Vulgar Latin <i>pipio,</i><br>
 
words undergo (cf. <i>pigeon</i>, ultimately from Vulgar Latin <i>pipio,</i><br>
derived in turn from an onomatopoeic formation): obvious proof<br>
+
derived in turn from an onomatopoeic [[formation]]): obvious proof<br>
  
that they lose something of their original character in order to<br>
+
that they lose something of their original [[character]] in [[order]] to<br>
 
assume that of the linguistic sign in general, which is unmotivated.<br><br>
 
assume that of the linguistic sign in general, which is unmotivated.<br><br>
  
 
     2) <i>Interjections</i>, closely related to onomatopoeia, can be at-<br>
 
     2) <i>Interjections</i>, closely related to onomatopoeia, can be at-<br>
 
tacked on the same grounds and come no closer to refuting our<br>
 
tacked on the same grounds and come no closer to refuting our<br>
thesis. One is tempted to see in them spontaneous expressions of<br>
+
[[thesis]]. One is tempted to see in them spontaneous expressions of<br>
reality dictated, so to speak, by natural forces. But for most inter-<br>
+
reality dictated, so to [[speak]], by natural forces. But for most inter-<br>
 
jectlons we can show that there is no fixed bond between their sig-<br>
 
jectlons we can show that there is no fixed bond between their sig-<br>
  
Line 261: Line 261:
 
guage to the next (e.g. the English equivalent of French <i>aie!</i> is<br>
 
guage to the next (e.g. the English equivalent of French <i>aie!</i> is<br>
 
ouch!). We know, moreover, that many interjections were once<br>
 
ouch!). We know, moreover, that many interjections were once<br>
words with specific meanings (cf. French <i>diable!</i> 'darn!' <i>mordieu!</i><br>
+
words with specific [[meanings]] (cf. French <i>diable!</i> 'darn!' <i>mordieu!</i><br>
  
'golly!' from <i>mort Dieu</i> 'God's death,' etc.).'<br><br>
+
'golly!' from <i>[[mort]] Dieu</i> 'God's [[death]],' etc.).'<br><br>
  
 
     Onomatopoeic formations and interjections are of secondary<br>
 
     Onomatopoeic formations and interjections are of secondary<br>
irnportance, and their symbolic origin is in part open to dispute.</font></p><p><font size="+1"><br>
+
irnportance, and their [[symbolic]] origin is in part open to dispute.</font></p><p><font size="+1"><br>
 
<br>
 
<br>
  
Line 274: Line 274:
 
which it gets the following characteristics: (a) it represents a span,<br>
 
which it gets the following characteristics: (a) it represents a span,<br>
 
and (b) the span is measurable in a single dimension; it is a line.<br>
 
and (b) the span is measurable in a single dimension; it is a line.<br>
While Principle II is obvious, apparently linguists have always<br>
+
While Principle II is obvious, apparently [[linguists]] have always<br>
neglected to state it, doubtless because they found it too simple;<br>
+
neglected to [[state]] it, doubtless because they found it too simple;<br>
 
nevertheless, it is fundamental, and its consequences are incal-<br>
 
nevertheless, it is fundamental, and its consequences are incal-<br>
 
culable. Its importance equals that of Principle I; the whole<br>
 
culable. Its importance equals that of Principle I; the whole<br>
mechanism of language depends upon it (see p. 122 f.). In contrast<br>
+
[[mechanism]] of language depends upon it (see p. 122 f.). In contrast<br>
  
to visual signifiers (nautical signals, etc.) which can offer simul-<br>
+
to [[visual]] [[signifiers]] (nautical signals, etc.) which can offer simul-<br>
 
taneous groupings in several dimensions, auditory signifiers have<br>
 
taneous groupings in several dimensions, auditory signifiers have<br>
at their command only the dimension of time. Their elements are<br>
+
at their command only the dimension of [[time]]. Their elements are<br>
presented in succession; they form a chain. This feature becomes<br>
+
presented in succession; they [[form]] a [[chain]]. This feature becomes<br>
readily apparent when they are represented in writing and the<br>
+
readily [[apparent]] when they are represented in [[writing]] and the<br>
 
spatial line of graphic marks is substituted for succession in time.<br><br>
 
spatial line of graphic marks is substituted for succession in time.<br><br>
  
Line 291: Line 291:
  
 
more than one significant element on the same point. But this is an<br>
 
more than one significant element on the same point. But this is an<br>
illusion; the syllable and its accent constitute only one phonational<br>
+
[[illusion]]; the syllable and its accent constitute only one phonational<br>
act. There is no duality within the act but only different op-<br>
+
act. There is no [[duality]] within the act but only different op-<br>
positions to what precedes and what follows (on this subject, see<br>
+
positions to what precedes and what follows (on this [[subject]], see<br>
 
p. 131).</font></p><p><font size="+1"><br>
 
p. 131).</font></p><p><font size="+1"><br>
 
<br>
 
<br>
Line 303: Line 303:
 
     The signifier, tbough to all appearances freely chosen with re-<br>
 
     The signifier, tbough to all appearances freely chosen with re-<br>
 
spect to the idea that it represcnts, iæ fixed, not free, with respect<br>
 
spect to the idea that it represcnts, iæ fixed, not free, with respect<br>
to the linguistic community that uses it. The masses have no voice<br>
+
to the linguistic community that uses it. The masses have no [[voice]]<br>
 
in the matter, and the signifier chosen by language could be re-<br>
 
in the matter, and the signifier chosen by language could be re-<br>
 
placed by no other. This fact, which seems to embody a contradic-<br>
 
placed by no other. This fact, which seems to embody a contradic-<br>
Line 311: Line 311:
  
 
way at all the choice that hag been made; and what is more, the<br>
 
way at all the choice that hag been made; and what is more, the<br>
community itself cannot control so much as a single word; it is<br>
+
community itself cannot [[control]] so much as a single word; it is<br>
 
bound to the existing language.<br><br>
 
bound to the existing language.<br><br>
  
 
     No longer can language be identified with a contract pure and<br>
 
     No longer can language be identified with a contract pure and<br>
 
simple, and it is precisely from this viewpoint that the linguistic<br>
 
simple, and it is precisely from this viewpoint that the linguistic<br>
sign is a particularly interesting object of study; for language<br>
+
sign is a particularly interesting [[object]] of study; for language<br>
 
furnishes the best proof that a law accepted by a community is a<br>
 
furnishes the best proof that a law accepted by a community is a<br>
 
thing that is tolerated and not a rule to which all freely consent.<br>
 
thing that is tolerated and not a rule to which all freely consent.<br>
Line 327: Line 327:
 
guage always appears as a heritage of the preceding period. We<br>
 
guage always appears as a heritage of the preceding period. We<br>
 
might conceive of an act by which, at a given moment, names were<br>
 
might conceive of an act by which, at a given moment, names were<br>
assigned to things and a contract was formed between concepts<br>
+
assigned to things and a contract was formed between [[concepts]]<br>
 
and sound-images; but such an act has never been recorded. The<br>
 
and sound-images; but such an act has never been recorded. The<br>
  
notion that things might have happened like that was prompted<br>
+
[[notion]] that things might have happened like that was prompted<br>
by our acute awareness of the arbitrary nature of the sign-<br><br>
+
by our acute [[awareness]] of the arbitrary nature of the sign-<br><br>
  
 
     No society, in fact, knows or has ever known language other than<br>
 
     No society, in fact, knows or has ever known language other than<br>
Line 337: Line 337:
 
accepted as such. That is why the question of the origin of speech<br>
 
accepted as such. That is why the question of the origin of speech<br>
 
is not so important as it is generally assumed to be. The question<br>
 
is not so important as it is generally assumed to be. The question<br>
is not even worth asking; the only real object of linguistics is the<br>
+
is not even worth asking; the only [[real]] object of linguistics is the<br>
normal, regular life of an existing idiom. A particular language-<br>
+
normal, regular [[life]] of an existing idiom. A particular language-<br>
  
 
state is always the product of historical forces, and these forces<br>
 
state is always the product of historical forces, and these forces<br>
 
explain why the sign is unchangeable, i.e. why it resists any<br>
 
explain why the sign is unchangeable, i.e. why it resists any<br>
arbitrary substitution.<br><br>
+
arbitrary [[substitution]].<br><br>
  
 
     Nothing is explained by saying that language is something<br>
 
     Nothing is explained by saying that language is something<br>
Line 350: Line 350:
 
     To meet that objection, we must put language into its social<br>
 
     To meet that objection, we must put language into its social<br>
  
setting and frame the question just as we would for any other<br>
+
setting and [[frame]] the question just as we would for any other<br>
 
social institution. How are other social ingtitutions transmitted?<br>
 
social institution. How are other social ingtitutions transmitted?<br>
 
This more general question includes the question of immutability.<br>
 
This more general question includes the question of immutability.<br>
We must first determine the greater or lesser amounts of freedom<br>
+
We must first determine the greater or lesser amounts of [[freedom]]<br>
that the other institutions enjoy; in each instance it will be seen<br>
+
that the other institutions [[enjoy]]; in each instance it will be seen<br>
that a different proportion exists between fixed tradition and the<br>
+
that a different proportion [[exists]] between fixed [[tradition]] and the<br>
free action of society. The next step is to discover why in a given<br>
+
free [[action]] of society. The next step is to discover why in a given<br>
category, the forces of the first type carry more weight or less<br>
+
[[category]], the forces of the first type carry more weight or less<br>
 
weight than those of the second. Finally, coming back to language,<br>
 
weight than those of the second. Finally, coming back to language,<br>
  
Line 365: Line 365:
 
     There are many possible answers to the question. For example,<br>
 
     There are many possible answers to the question. For example,<br>
 
one might point to the fact that succeeding generations are not<br>
 
one might point to the fact that succeeding generations are not<br>
superimposed on one another like the drawers of a piece of furni-<br>
+
superimposed on one [[another]] like the drawers of a piece of furni-<br>
 
ture, but fuse and interpenetrate, each generation embracing in-<br>
 
ture, but fuse and interpenetrate, each generation embracing in-<br>
 
dividuals of all ages‹with the result that modifications of language<br>
 
dividuals of all ages‹with the result that modifications of language<br>
are not tied to the succession of generations. One might also recall<br>
+
are not tied to the succession of generations. One might also [[recall]]<br>
  
the sum of the efforts required for learning the mother language<br>
+
the sum of the efforts required for learning the [[mother]] language<br>
and conclude that a general change would be impossible. Again,<br>
+
and conclude that a general change would be [[impossible]]. Again,<br>
it might be added that reflection does not enter into the active use<br>
+
it might be added that [[reflection]] does not enter into the [[active]] use<br>
of an idiom‹speakers are largely unconscious of the laws of lan-<br>
+
of an idiom‹speakers are largely [[unconscious]] of the laws of lan-<br>
 
guage; and if they are unaware of them, how could they modify<br>
 
guage; and if they are unaware of them, how could they modify<br>
 
them? Even if they were aware of these laws, we may be sure that<br>
 
them? Even if they were aware of these laws, we may be sure that<br>
their awareness would seldom lead to criticism, for people are<br>
+
their awareness would seldom lead to criticism, for [[people]] are<br>
 
generally satisfied with the language they have received.<br><br>
 
generally satisfied with the language they have received.<br><br>
  
Line 384: Line 384:
  
 
     1) The arbitrary nature of the sign. Above, we had to accept the<br>
 
     1) The arbitrary nature of the sign. Above, we had to accept the<br>
theoretical possibility of change; further reflection suggests that<br>
+
[[theoretical]] possibility of change; further reflection suggests that<br>
 
the arbitrary nature of the sign is really what protects language<br>
 
the arbitrary nature of the sign is really what protects language<br>
from any attempt to modify it. Even if people were more conscious<br>
+
from any attempt to modify it. Even if people were more [[conscious]]<br>
  
 
of language than they are, they would still not know how to discuss<br>
 
of language than they are, they would still not know how to discuss<br>
it. The reason is simply that any subject in order to be discussed<br>
+
it. The [[reason]] is simply that any subject in order to be discussed<br>
 
must have a reasonable basis. It is possible, for instance, to discuss<br>
 
must have a reasonable basis. It is possible, for instance, to discuss<br>
whether the monogamous form of marriage is more reasonable than<br>
+
whether the monogamous form of [[marriage]] is more reasonable than<br>
 
the polygamous form and to advance arguments to support either<br>
 
the polygamous form and to advance arguments to support either<br>
side. One could also argue about a system of symbols, for the sym-<br>
+
side. One could also argue [[about]] a system of [[symbols]], for the sym-<br>
bol has a rational relationship with the thing signified (see p. 68);<br>
+
bol has a [[rational]] [[relationship]] with [[the thing]] signified (see p. 68);<br>
but language is a system of arbitrary signs and lacks the necessary<br>
+
but language is a system of arbitrary signs and [[lacks]] the necessary<br>
basis, the solid ground for discussion. There is no reason for<br>
+
basis, the solid ground for [[discussion]]. There is no reason for<br>
  
 
preferring <i>soeur</i> to <i>sister</i>, <i>Ochs</i> to <i>boeuf,</i> etc.<br><br>
 
preferring <i>soeur</i> to <i>sister</i>, <i>Ochs</i> to <i>boeuf,</i> etc.<br><br>
Line 412: Line 412:
  
 
system. In this one respect (as we shall see later) language is not<br>
 
system. In this one respect (as we shall see later) language is not<br>
completely arbitrary but is ruled to some extent by logic; it is<br>
+
completely arbitrary but is ruled to some extent by [[logic]]; it is<br>
 
here also, however, that the inability of the masses to transform<br>
 
here also, however, that the inability of the masses to transform<br>
 
it becomes apparcnt. The system is a complex mechanism that can<br>
 
it becomes apparcnt. The system is a complex mechanism that can<br>
 
be grasped only through reflection; the very ones who use it daily<br>
 
be grasped only through reflection; the very ones who use it daily<br>
 
are ignorant of it. We can conceive of a change only through the<br>
 
are ignorant of it. We can conceive of a change only through the<br>
intervention of specialists, grammarians, logicians, etc.; but ex-<br>
+
[[intervention]] of specialists, grammarians, logicians, etc.; but ex-<br>
 
perience shows us that all such meddlings have failed.<br><br>
 
perience shows us that all such meddlings have failed.<br><br>
  
 
     4) <i>Collective inertia toward innovation</i>. Language‹and this con-<br>
 
     4) <i>Collective inertia toward innovation</i>. Language‹and this con-<br>
 
sideration surpasses all the others‹is at every moment every-<br>
 
sideration surpasses all the others‹is at every moment every-<br>
body's concern; spread throughout society and manipulated by it,<br>
+
[[body]]'s concern; spread throughout society and manipulated by it,<br>
 
language is something used daily by all. Here we are unable to set<br>
 
language is something used daily by all. Here we are unable to set<br>
 
up any comparison between it and other institutions- The pre-<br>
 
up any comparison between it and other institutions- The pre-<br>
scriptions of codes, religious rites, nautical signals, etc., involve<br>
+
scriptions of [[codes]], [[religious]] rites, nautical signals, etc., involve<br>
 
only a certain number of individuals simultaneously and then only<br>
 
only a certain number of individuals simultaneously and then only<br>
  
 
during a limited period of time; in language, on the contrary, every-<br>
 
during a limited period of time; in language, on the contrary, every-<br>
one participates at all times, and that is why it is constantly being<br>
+
one participates at all times, and that is why it is constantly [[being]]<br>
influenced by all. This capital fact suffices to show the impossibility<br>
+
influenced by all. This [[capital]] fact suffices to show the [[impossibility]]<br>
of revolution. Of all social institutions, language is least amenable<br>
+
of [[revolution]]. Of all [[social institutions]], language is least amenable<br>
 
to initiative. It blends with the life of society, and the latter, inert<br>
 
to initiative. It blends with the life of society, and the latter, inert<br>
by nature, is a prime conservative force.<br><br>
+
by nature, is a prime [[conservative]] force.<br><br>
  
 
     But to say that language is a product of social forces does not<br>
 
     But to say that language is a product of social forces does not<br>
suffice to show clearly that it is unfree; remembering that it is<br>
+
suffice to show clearly that it is unfree; [[remembering]] that it is<br>
  
 
always the heritage of the preceding period, we must add that these<br>
 
always the heritage of the preceding period, we must add that these<br>
 
social forces are linked with time. Language is checked not only by<br>
 
social forces are linked with time. Language is checked not only by<br>
 
the weight of the collectivity but also by time. These two are in-<br>
 
the weight of the collectivity but also by time. These two are in-<br>
separable. At every moment solidarity with the past checks free-<br>
+
separable. At every moment [[solidarity]] with the [[past]] checks free-<br>
 
dom of choice. We say <i>man</i> and <i>dog</i>. This does not prevent the<br>
 
dom of choice. We say <i>man</i> and <i>dog</i>. This does not prevent the<br>
existence in the total phenomenon of a bond between the two<br>
+
existence in the [[total]] phenomenon of a bond between the two<br>
  
 
antithetical forces‹arbitrary convention by virtue of which choice<br>
 
antithetical forces‹arbitrary convention by virtue of which choice<br>
Line 468: Line 468:
 
into detail, let us see what things need to be delineated.<br>
 
into detail, let us see what things need to be delineated.<br>
 
First, let there be no mistake about the meaning that we attach<br>
 
First, let there be no mistake about the meaning that we attach<br>
to the word change. One might think that it deals especially with<br>
+
to the word change. One might [[think]] that it deals especially with<br>
 
phonetic changes undergone by the signifier, or perhaps changes in<br>
 
phonetic changes undergone by the signifier, or perhaps changes in<br>
meaning which affect the signified concept. That view would be<br>
+
meaning which [[affect]] the signified concept. That view would be<br>
 
inadequate. Regardless of what the forces of change are, whether<br>
 
inadequate. Regardless of what the forces of change are, whether<br>
  
in isolation or in combination, they always result in <i>a shift in the<br>
+
in [[isolation]] or in combination, they always result in <i>a shift in the<br>
 
relationship between the signified and the signifer.</i><br><br>
 
relationship between the signified and the signifer.</i><br><br>
  
Line 479: Line 479:
 
in French. Both the gound-image and the concept changed; but it<br>
 
in French. Both the gound-image and the concept changed; but it<br>
  
is useless to separate the two parts of the phenomenon; it is<br>
+
is useless to [[separate]] the two parts of the phenomenon; it is<br>
 
sufficient to state with respect to the whole that the bond between<br>
 
sufficient to state with respect to the whole that the bond between<br>
 
the idea and the sign was loosened, and that there was a shift in<br>
 
the idea and the sign was loosened, and that there was a shift in<br>
Line 494: Line 494:
  
 
ship was changed in two ways: the signifier was changed not only<br>
 
ship was changed in two ways: the signifier was changed not only<br>
in its material aspect but also in its grammatical form; the idea of<br>
+
in its material aspect but also in its [[grammatical]] form; the idea of<br>
 
<i>Teil</i> 'part' is no longer implied; <i>Drittel</i> is a simple word. In one way<br>
 
<i>Teil</i> 'part' is no longer implied; <i>Drittel</i> is a simple word. In one way<br>
 
or another there is always a shift in the relationship.<br><br>
 
or another there is always a shift in the relationship.<br><br>
Line 512: Line 512:
 
     Unlike language, other human institutions‹customs, laws, etc.<br>
 
     Unlike language, other human institutions‹customs, laws, etc.<br>
 
‹are all based in varying degrees on the natural relations of things;<br>
 
‹are all based in varying degrees on the natural relations of things;<br>
all have of necessity adapted the means employed to the ends<br>
+
all have of [[necessity]] adapted the means employed to the ends<br>
  
 
pursued. Even fashion in dress is not entirely arbitrary; we can<br>
 
pursued. Even fashion in dress is not entirely arbitrary; we can<br>
deviate only slightly from the conditions dictated by the human<br>
+
deviate only slightly from the [[conditions]] dictated by the [[human]]<br>
body. Language is limited by nothing in the choice of means, for<br>
+
body. Language is limited by [[nothing]] in the choice of means, for<br>
 
apparently nothing would prevent the associating of any idea<br>
 
apparently nothing would prevent the associating of any idea<br>
 
whatsoever with just any sequence of sounds.<br><br>
 
whatsoever with just any sequence of sounds.<br><br>
Line 542: Line 542:
 
     Mutability is so inescapable that it even holds true for artificial<br>
 
     Mutability is so inescapable that it even holds true for artificial<br>
 
languages. Whoever creates a language controls it only so long as<br>
 
languages. Whoever creates a language controls it only so long as<br>
it is not in circulation; from the moment when it fulfills its mission<br>
+
it is not in [[circulation]]; from the moment when it fulfills its mission<br>
  
 
and becomes the property of everyone, control is lost. Take Es-<br>
 
and becomes the property of everyone, control is lost. Take Es-<br>
Line 548: Line 548:
 
law? Once launched, it is quite likely that Esperanto will enter<br>
 
law? Once launched, it is quite likely that Esperanto will enter<br>
 
upon a fully semiological life; it will be transmitted according to<br>
 
upon a fully semiological life; it will be transmitted according to<br>
laws which have nothing in common with those of its logical cre-<br>
+
laws which have nothing in common with those of its [[logical]] cre-<br>
 
ation, and there will be no turning backwards. A man proposing<br>
 
ation, and there will be no turning backwards. A man proposing<br>
 
a fixed language that posterity would have to accept for what it is<br>
 
a fixed language that posterity would have to accept for what it is<br>
Line 561: Line 561:
  
 
     But what supports the necessity for change? I might be re-<br>
 
     But what supports the necessity for change? I might be re-<br>
proached for not having been as explicit on this point as on the<br>
+
proached for not having been as [[explicit]] on this point as on the<br>
 
principle of immutability. This is because I failed to distinguish<br>
 
principle of immutability. This is because I failed to distinguish<br>
  
 
between the different forces of change. We must consider their<br>
 
between the different forces of change. We must consider their<br>
great variety in order to understand the extent to which they are<br>
+
great variety in order to [[understand]] the extent to which they are<br>
 
necessary.<br><br>
 
necessary.<br><br>
  
 
     The causes of continuity are <i>a priori </i>within the scope of the<br>
 
     The causes of continuity are <i>a priori </i>within the scope of the<br>
observer, but the causes of change in time are not. It is better not<br>
+
[[observer]], but the causes of change in time are not. It is better not<br>
 
to attempt giving an exact account at this point, but to restrict<br>
 
to attempt giving an exact account at this point, but to restrict<br>
 
discussion to the shifting of relationships in general. Time changes<br>
 
discussion to the shifting of relationships in general. Time changes<br>
Line 584: Line 584:
  
 
of linguistic habits which allow an individual to understand and<br>
 
of linguistic habits which allow an individual to understand and<br>
to be understood.</font></p><p><font size="+1"><br>
+
to be [[understood]].</font></p><p><font size="+1"><br>
  
 
     2) But this definition still leaves language outside its social con-<br>
 
     2) But this definition still leaves language outside its social con-<br>
text; it makes language something artificial since it includes only<br>
+
[[text]]; it makes language something artificial since it includes only<br>
 
the individual part of reality; for the realization of language, a<br>
 
the individual part of reality; for the realization of language, a<br>
 
community of speakers [<i>masse parlante</i>] is necessary. Contrary to<br>
 
community of speakers [<i>masse parlante</i>] is necessary. Contrary to<br>
Line 593: Line 593:
  
 
for it is a semiological phenomenon. Its social nature is one of its<br>
 
for it is a semiological phenomenon. Its social nature is one of its<br>
inner characteristics. Its complete definition confronts us with two<br>
+
inner characteristics. Its [[complete]] definition confronts us with two<br>
 
inseparable entities, as shown in this drawing:</font></p><p>
 
inseparable entities, as shown in this drawing:</font></p><p>
 
</p><p>
 
</p><p>
Line 615: Line 615:
 
nature, considered independently, does not definitely rule out this<br>
 
nature, considered independently, does not definitely rule out this<br>
 
viewpoint. Doubtless it is not on a purely logical basis that group<br>
 
viewpoint. Doubtless it is not on a purely logical basis that group<br>
psychology operates; one must consider everything that deflects<br>
+
[[psychology]] operates; one must consider everything that deflects<br>
  
 
reason in actual contacts between individuals. But the thing which<br>
 
reason in actual contacts between individuals. But the thing which<br>
Line 625: Line 625:
  
 
     If we congidered language in time, without the community of<br>
 
     If we congidered language in time, without the community of<br>
speakers--imagine an isolated individual living for several cen-<br>
+
speakers--imagine an isolated individual [[living]] for several cen-<br>
  
 
turies‹we probably would notice no change; time would not<br>
 
turies‹we probably would notice no change; time would not<br>
 
influence language. Conversely, if we considered the community<br>
 
influence language. Conversely, if we considered the community<br>
 
of speakers without considering time, we would not see the effect<br>
 
of speakers without considering time, we would not see the effect<br>
of the social forces that influence language. To represent the actual<br>
+
of the social forces that influence language. To [[represent]] the actual<br>
 
facts, we must then add to our first drawing a sign to indicate<br>
 
facts, we must then add to our first drawing a sign to indicate<br>
 
passage of time:<br><br>
 
passage of time:<br><br>
Line 639: Line 639:
 
     Language is no longer free, for time will allow the social forces<br>
 
     Language is no longer free, for time will allow the social forces<br>
  
at work on it to carry out their effects. This brings us back to the<br>
+
at [[work]] on it to carry out their effects. This brings us back to the<br>
 
principle of continuity, which cancels freedom. But continuity<br>
 
principle of continuity, which cancels freedom. But continuity<br>
 
necessarily implies change, varying degrees of shifts in the relation<br>
 
necessarily implies change, varying degrees of shifts in the relation<br>
Line 645: Line 645:
 
<br>
 
<br>
 
(from Saussure's <i>Course in
 
(from Saussure's <i>Course in
General Linguistics</i> (Phil Library, 1966)  pp. 65-78.)</font>
+
General Linguistics</i> (Phil [[Library]], 1966)  pp. 65-78.)</font>

Latest revision as of 22:34, 20 May 2019

NATURE OF THE LINGUISTIC SIGN



[[[Saussure]] introduces the structuralist point of view into

linguistics which is marked first of all by giving special relief to the synchronic dimension in the study of language. The synchronic dimension is distinguished from the diachronic, that is, historic. The idea is that an account of the present meaning of words and sentences, i.e. semantics, can't be reduced to a historical study. This may seem obvious to us, but the study of linguistic meaning prior to Saussure had been historical with considerations of structure limited largely to a consideration of grammar. The idea is that meaning, or signification, depends on the SYSTEM of language given by a number of laws of equilibrium which constitute the relative systemic stability of linguistic meaning at the moment when, in virtue of this system, one speaks. So we have the distinction between la langue and la parole. Language is the articulated use of the system, la langue

in speech, la parole. La langue is language minus la parole. It is difficult to overestimate the significance of Saussure's idea for a whole generation of French thinkers. For insofar as language enters into the determination of a whole variety of social phenomena, its effects as structure enter in as well. Post structuralist thinkers remain in debt to Saussure for however dynamic and open-textured structures come to be, one can't go back to purely historical modes of interpretation. The structuring effects of discourse, the agency of the

letter in Lacan's terms, must be taken into account.]




1. Sign, Signified, Signifier

Some people regard language, when reduced to its elements, as
a naming-process only‹a list of words, each corresponding to the

thing that it names. For example:




<img src="saussure1.jpeg" height="0" width="0">





This conception is open to criticism at several points. It assumes
that ready-made ideas exist before words (on this point, see below,
p. 111); it does not tell us whether a name is vocal or psychological
in nature (arbor, for instance, can be considered from either view-
point); finally, it lets us assume that the linking of a name and a
thing is a very simple operation‹an assumption that is anything
but true. But this rather naive approach can bring us near the
truth by showing us that the linguistic unit is a double entity, one
formed by the associating of two terms

We have seen in considering the speaking-circuit (p. 11) that both terms involved in the linguistic sign are psychological and are
united in the brain by an assocative bond- This point must be
emphasized.

The linguistic sign unites, not a thing and a name, but a concept
and a sound-image.[l] The latter is not the material sound, a purely
physical thing, but the psychological imprint of the sound, the
impression that it makes on our senses. The sound-image is sensory,
and if I happen to call it "material,"' it is only in that sense, and by
way of opposing it to the other term of the association, the concept,
which is generally more abstract.

The psychological character of our sound-images becomes ap-
parent when we observe our own speech. Without moving our lips
or tongue, we can talk to ourselves or recite mentally a selection of
verse. Because we regard the words of our language as sound-
images, we must avoid speaking of the "phonemes" that make up
the words. This term, which suggests vocal activity, is applicable
to the spoken word only, to the realization of the inner image in
discourse. We can avoid that misunderstanding by speaking of the
sounds and syllables of a word provided we remember that the
names refer to the sound-image.

The linguistic sign is then a two-sided psychological entity that
can be represented by the drawing:



<img src="saussure2.jpeg" height="0" width="0">

The two elements are intimately united, and each recalls the
other. Whether we try to find the meaning of the Latin word arbor

or the word that Latin uses to designate the concept "tree," it is



1. The term sound-image may seem to be too restricted inasmuch as beside
the representation of the sounds of a word there is also that of its articulation,

tbe muscular image of the phonational act. But for F. de Saussure language is
essentially a depository, a thing received from without (see p. 13). The sound
image is par excellence the natural representation of the word as a fact of
potential language, outside any actual use of it in speaking. The motor side is
thus implied or, in any event, occupies only a subordinate role with respect

to the sound-image. [Ed.]









clear that only the associations sanctioned by that language appeal
to us to conform to reality, and we disregard whatever others
might be imagined.

Our definition of the linguistic sign poses an important question
of terminology. I call the combination of a concept and a sound-
image a sign, but in current usage the term generally designates

only a sound-image, a word, for example (arbor, etc.). One tends
to forget that arbor is called a sign only because it carries the con-
cept "tree," with the result that the idea of the sensory part

implies the idea of the whole.



<img src="saussure3.jpeg" height="0" width="0">





Ambiguity would disappear if the three notions involved here
were designated by three names, each suggesting and opposing the
others. I propose to retain the word sign [[[signe]]] to designate the
whole and to replace concept and sound-image respectively by

signified [signifié] and signifier [[[signifiant]]]; the last two terms have
the advantage of indicating the opposition that separates them
from each other and from the whole of which they are parts. As
regards sign, if I am satisfied with it, this is simply because I do not
know of any word to replace it, the ordinary language suggesting
no other.

The linguistic sign, as defined, has two primordial character-
istics. In enunciating them I am also positing the basic principles of

any study of this type.


2. Principle 1: The Arbitrary Nature of the Sign

The bond between the signifier and the signified is arbitrary.
Since I mean by sign the whole that results from the associating of

the signifier with the signified, I can simply say: the linguistic sign
is arbitrary.


The idea of "sister" is not linked by any inner relationship to
the succession of sounds s-ö-r which serves as its signifier in French;
that it could be represented equally by just any other sequence is
proved by differences among languages and by the very existence

of different languages: the signified "ox" has as its signifier b-ô-f
on one side of the border and o-k-s (Ochs) on the other.

No one disputes the principle of the arbitrary nature of the sign,
but it is often easier to discover a truth than to assign to it its
proper place. Principle I dominates all the linguistics of language;
its consequences are numberless. It is true that not all of them are

equally obvious at first glance; only after many detours does one
discover them, and with them the primordial importance of the
principle.

One remark in passing: when semiology becomes organized as
a science, the question will arise whether or not it properly includes
modes of expression based on completely natural signs, such as
pantomime. Supposing that the new science welcomes them, its
main concern will still be the whole group of systems grounded on

the arbitrariness of the sign. In fact, every means of expression used
in society is based, in principle, on collective behavior or‹what
amounts to the same thing‹on convention. Polite formulas, for
instance, though often imbued with a certain natural expressive-
ness (as in the case of a Chinese who greets his emperor by bowing
down to the ground nine times), are nonetheless fixed by rule; it is
this rule and not the intrinsic value of the gestures that obliges one
to use them. Signs that are wholly arbitrary realize better than the
others the ideal of the semiological process; that is why language,

the most complex and universal of all systems of expression, is also
the most characteristic; in this sense linguistics can become the
master-pattern for all branches of semiology although language is
only one particular semiological system.

The word symbol has been used to designate the linguistic sign,
or more specifically, what is here called the signifier. Principle I in

particular weighs against the use of this term. One characteristic
of the symbol is that it is never wholly arbitrary; it is not empty,
for there is the rudiment of a natural bond between the signifier
and the signified. The symbol of justice, a pair of scales, could not
be replaced by just any other symbol, such as a chariot.

The word arbitrary also calls ior commcnt. The term should not

imply that the choice of the signifier is left entirely to the speaker
(we shall see below that the individual does not have the power to
change a sign in any way once it has become established in the
linguistic community); I mean that it is unmotivated, i.e. arbitrary
in that it actually has no natural connection with the signified.
In concluding let us consider two objections that might be raised
to the establishment of Principle I:

1) Onomatopoeia might be used to prove that the choice of the

signifier is not always arbitrary. But onomatopoeic formations are
never organic elements of a linguistic system. Besides, their number
is much smaller than is generally supposed. Words like French
fouet 'whip' or glas 'knell' may strike certain ears with suggestive
sonority, but to see that they have not always had this property
we need only examine their Latin forms (fouet is derived from fagus

'beech-tree,' glas from classicum 'sound of a trumpet'). The quality
of their present sounds, or rather the quality that is attributed to
them, is a fortuitous result of phonetic evolution.

As for authentic onomatopoeic words (e.g. glug~glug, tick-tock,
etc.), not only are they limited in number, but also they are chosen

somewhat arbitrarily, for they are only approximate and more or
less conventional imitations of certain sounds (cf. English bo~boto
and French ouaoua). In addition, once these words have been intro-
duced into the language, they are to a certain extent subjected to
the same evolution‹phonetic, morphological, etc.‹that other
words undergo (cf. pigeon, ultimately from Vulgar Latin pipio,
derived in turn from an onomatopoeic formation): obvious proof

that they lose something of their original character in order to
assume that of the linguistic sign in general, which is unmotivated.

2) Interjections, closely related to onomatopoeia, can be at-
tacked on the same grounds and come no closer to refuting our
thesis. One is tempted to see in them spontaneous expressions of
reality dictated, so to speak, by natural forces. But for most inter-
jectlons we can show that there is no fixed bond between their sig-

nified and their signifier. We need only compare two languages on
this point to see how much such expressions differ from one lan-
guage to the next (e.g. the English equivalent of French aie! is
ouch!). We know, moreover, that many interjections were once
words with specific meanings (cf. French diable! 'darn!' mordieu!

'golly!' from mort Dieu 'God's death,' etc.).'

Onomatopoeic formations and interjections are of secondary

irnportance, and their symbolic origin is in part open to dispute.



3. Principle II: The Linear Nature of the Signifier

The signifier, being auditory, is unfolded solely in time from
which it gets the following characteristics: (a) it represents a span,
and (b) the span is measurable in a single dimension; it is a line.
While Principle II is obvious, apparently linguists have always
neglected to state it, doubtless because they found it too simple;
nevertheless, it is fundamental, and its consequences are incal-
culable. Its importance equals that of Principle I; the whole
mechanism of language depends upon it (see p. 122 f.). In contrast

to visual signifiers (nautical signals, etc.) which can offer simul-
taneous groupings in several dimensions, auditory signifiers have
at their command only the dimension of time. Their elements are
presented in succession; they form a chain. This feature becomes
readily apparent when they are represented in writing and the
spatial line of graphic marks is substituted for succession in time.

Sometimes the linear nature of the signifier is not obvious. When
I accent a syllable, for instance, it seems that I am concentrating

more than one significant element on the same point. But this is an
illusion; the syllable and its accent constitute only one phonational
act. There is no duality within the act but only different op-
positions to what precedes and what follows (on this subject, see

p. 131).



IMMUTABILITY AND MUTABILITY OF THE SIGN


1. Immutability

The signifier, tbough to all appearances freely chosen with re-
spect to the idea that it represcnts, iæ fixed, not free, with respect
to the linguistic community that uses it. The masses have no voice
in the matter, and the signifier chosen by language could be re-
placed by no other. This fact, which seems to embody a contradic-
tion, might be called colloquially "the stacked deck." We say to
language: "Choose!" but we add: "It must be this sign and no
other." No individual, even if he willed it, could modify in any

way at all the choice that hag been made; and what is more, the
community itself cannot control so much as a single word; it is
bound to the existing language.

No longer can language be identified with a contract pure and
simple, and it is precisely from this viewpoint that the linguistic
sign is a particularly interesting object of study; for language
furnishes the best proof that a law accepted by a community is a
thing that is tolerated and not a rule to which all freely consent.

Let us first see why we cannot control the linguistic sign and then
draw together the important consequences that issue from the
phenomenon.

No matter what period we chooge or how far back we go, lan-
guage always appears as a heritage of the preceding period. We
might conceive of an act by which, at a given moment, names were
assigned to things and a contract was formed between concepts
and sound-images; but such an act has never been recorded. The

notion that things might have happened like that was prompted
by our acute awareness of the arbitrary nature of the sign-

No society, in fact, knows or has ever known language other than
as a product inherited from preceding generations, and one to be
accepted as such. That is why the question of the origin of speech
is not so important as it is generally assumed to be. The question
is not even worth asking; the only real object of linguistics is the
normal, regular life of an existing idiom. A particular language-

state is always the product of historical forces, and these forces
explain why the sign is unchangeable, i.e. why it resists any
arbitrary substitution.

Nothing is explained by saying that language is something
inherited and leaving it at that. Can not existing and inherited
laws be modified from one moment to the next?

To meet that objection, we must put language into its social

setting and frame the question just as we would for any other
social institution. How are other social ingtitutions transmitted?
This more general question includes the question of immutability.
We must first determine the greater or lesser amounts of freedom
that the other institutions enjoy; in each instance it will be seen
that a different proportion exists between fixed tradition and the
free action of society. The next step is to discover why in a given
category, the forces of the first type carry more weight or less
weight than those of the second. Finally, coming back to language,

we must ask why the historical factor of transmission dominates it
entirely and prohibits any sudden widespread change.

There are many possible answers to the question. For example,
one might point to the fact that succeeding generations are not
superimposed on one another like the drawers of a piece of furni-
ture, but fuse and interpenetrate, each generation embracing in-
dividuals of all ages‹with the result that modifications of language
are not tied to the succession of generations. One might also recall

the sum of the efforts required for learning the mother language
and conclude that a general change would be impossible. Again,
it might be added that reflection does not enter into the active use
of an idiom‹speakers are largely unconscious of the laws of lan-
guage; and if they are unaware of them, how could they modify
them? Even if they were aware of these laws, we may be sure that
their awareness would seldom lead to criticism, for people are
generally satisfied with the language they have received.

The foregoing considerations are important but not topical. The
following are more basic and direct, and all the others depend on
them.

1) The arbitrary nature of the sign. Above, we had to accept the
theoretical possibility of change; further reflection suggests that
the arbitrary nature of the sign is really what protects language
from any attempt to modify it. Even if people were more conscious

of language than they are, they would still not know how to discuss
it. The reason is simply that any subject in order to be discussed
must have a reasonable basis. It is possible, for instance, to discuss
whether the monogamous form of marriage is more reasonable than
the polygamous form and to advance arguments to support either
side. One could also argue about a system of symbols, for the sym-
bol has a rational relationship with the thing signified (see p. 68);
but language is a system of arbitrary signs and lacks the necessary
basis, the solid ground for discussion. There is no reason for

preferring soeur to sister, Ochs to boeuf, etc.

2) The multiplicity of signs necessary to form any language.

Another important deterrent to linguistic change is the great num-
ber of signs that must go into the making of any language. A
system of writing comprising twenty to forty letters can in case
of need be replaced by another system. The same would be true
of language if it contained a limited number of elements; but
linguistic signs are numberless.

3) The over-complexity of the system. A language constitutes a

system. In this one respect (as we shall see later) language is not
completely arbitrary but is ruled to some extent by logic; it is
here also, however, that the inability of the masses to transform
it becomes apparcnt. The system is a complex mechanism that can
be grasped only through reflection; the very ones who use it daily
are ignorant of it. We can conceive of a change only through the
intervention of specialists, grammarians, logicians, etc.; but ex-
perience shows us that all such meddlings have failed.

4) Collective inertia toward innovation. Language‹and this con-
sideration surpasses all the others‹is at every moment every-
body's concern; spread throughout society and manipulated by it,
language is something used daily by all. Here we are unable to set
up any comparison between it and other institutions- The pre-
scriptions of codes, religious rites, nautical signals, etc., involve
only a certain number of individuals simultaneously and then only

during a limited period of time; in language, on the contrary, every-
one participates at all times, and that is why it is constantly being
influenced by all. This capital fact suffices to show the impossibility
of revolution. Of all social institutions, language is least amenable
to initiative. It blends with the life of society, and the latter, inert
by nature, is a prime conservative force.

But to say that language is a product of social forces does not
suffice to show clearly that it is unfree; remembering that it is

always the heritage of the preceding period, we must add that these
social forces are linked with time. Language is checked not only by
the weight of the collectivity but also by time. These two are in-
separable. At every moment solidarity with the past checks free-
dom of choice. We say man and dog. This does not prevent the
existence in the total phenomenon of a bond between the two

antithetical forces‹arbitrary convention by virtue of which choice
is free and time which causes choice to be fixed. Because the sign
is arbitrary, it follows no law other than that of tradition, and

because it is based on tradition, it is arbitrary.


2. Mutability

Time, which insures the continuity of language, wields another
influence apparently contradictory to the first: the more or less

rapid change ol linguistic signs. In a certain sense, therefore, we
can speak of both the immutability and the mutability of the sign.'

In the last analysis, the two facts are interdependent: the sign
is exposed to alteration because it perpetuates itself. What pre-
dominates in all change is the persistence of the old substance;
disregard for the past is only relative. That is why the principle
of change is based on the principle of continuity.

Change in time takes many forms, on any one of which an im-
portant chapter in linguistics might be written. Without entering
into detail, let us see what things need to be delineated.
First, let there be no mistake about the meaning that we attach
to the word change. One might think that it deals especially with
phonetic changes undergone by the signifier, or perhaps changes in
meaning which affect the signified concept. That view would be
inadequate. Regardless of what the forces of change are, whether

in isolation or in combination, they always result in a shift in the
relationship between the signified and the signifer.


Here are some examples. Latin necare 'kill' became noyer 'drown'
in French. Both the gound-image and the concept changed; but it

is useless to separate the two parts of the phenomenon; it is
sufficient to state with respect to the whole that the bond between
the idea and the sign was loosened, and that there was a shift in
their relationship. If instead of comparing Classical Latin necare
with French noyer, we contrast the former term with necare of
Vulgar Latin of the fourth or fifth century meaning 'drown' the

case is a little different; but here again; although there is no
appreciable change in the signifier, there is a shift in the relation-
ship between the idea and the sign.'

Old German dritteil 'one-third' became Drittel in Modern Ger-
man. Here, although the concept remained the same, the relation-

ship was changed in two ways: the signifier was changed not only
in its material aspect but also in its grammatical form; the idea of
Teil 'part' is no longer implied; Drittel is a simple word. In one way
or another there is always a shift in the relationship.

In Anglo-Saxon the preliterary form fot 'foot' remained while its

plural foti became fet (Modern English feet). Regardless of the
other changes that are implied, one thing is certain: there was a
shift in their relationship; other correspondenceg between the
phonetic substance and the idea emerged.

Language is radically powerless to defend itself against the
forces which from one moment to the next are shifting the relation-
ship between the signified and the signifier. This is one of the
consequences of the arbitrary nature of the sign.

Unlike language, other human institutions‹customs, laws, etc.
‹are all based in varying degrees on the natural relations of things;
all have of necessity adapted the means employed to the ends

pursued. Even fashion in dress is not entirely arbitrary; we can
deviate only slightly from the conditions dictated by the human
body. Language is limited by nothing in the choice of means, for
apparently nothing would prevent the associating of any idea
whatsoever with just any sequence of sounds.

To emphasize the fact that language is a genuine institution,
Whitney quite justly insisted upon the arbitrary nature of signs;
and by so doing, he placed linguistics on its true axis. But he did

not follow through and see that the arbitrariness of language radi-
cally separates it from all other institutions. This is apparent from
the way in which language evolves. Nothing could be more com-
plex. As it is a product of both the social force and time, no one
can change anything in it, and on the other hand, the arbitrariness
of its signs theoretically entails the freedom of establishing just
any relationship between phonetic substance and ideas. The result
is that each of the two elements united in the sign maintains its
own life to a degree unknown elsewhere, and that language

changes, or rather evolves, under the influence of all the forces
which can affect either sounds or meanings. The evolution is in-
evitable; there is no example of a single language that resists it.
After a certain period of time, some obvious shifts can always be
recorded.

Mutability is so inescapable that it even holds true for artificial
languages. Whoever creates a language controls it only so long as
it is not in circulation; from the moment when it fulfills its mission

and becomes the property of everyone, control is lost. Take Es-
peranto as an example; if it succeeds, will it escape the inexorable
law? Once launched, it is quite likely that Esperanto will enter
upon a fully semiological life; it will be transmitted according to
laws which have nothing in common with those of its logical cre-
ation, and there will be no turning backwards. A man proposing
a fixed language that posterity would have to accept for what it is
would be like a hen hatching a duck's egg: the language created
by him would be borne along, willy-nilly, by the current that

engulfs all languages.

Signs are governed by a principle of general semiology: con-
tinuity in time is coupled to change in time; this is confirmed by
orthographic systems, the speech of deaf-mutes, etc.

But what supports the necessity for change? I might be re-
proached for not having been as explicit on this point as on the
principle of immutability. This is because I failed to distinguish

between the different forces of change. We must consider their
great variety in order to understand the extent to which they are
necessary.

The causes of continuity are a priori within the scope of the
observer, but the causes of change in time are not. It is better not
to attempt giving an exact account at this point, but to restrict
discussion to the shifting of relationships in general. Time changes

all things; there is no reason why language should escape this
universal law.

Let us review the main points of our discussion and relate them
to the principles set up in the Introduction.

1) Avoiding sterile word definitions, within the total phenome-
non represented by speech we first singled out two parts: language
and speaking. Language is speech less speaking. It is the whole set

of linguistic habits which allow an individual to understand and

to be understood.


2) But this definition still leaves language outside its social con-
text; it makes language something artificial since it includes only
the individual part of reality; for the realization of language, a
community of speakers [masse parlante] is necessary. Contrary to
all appearances, language never exists apart from the social fact,

for it is a semiological phenomenon. Its social nature is one of its
inner characteristics. Its complete definition confronts us with two

inseparable entities, as shown in this drawing:




<img src="saussure4.jpeg" height="0" width="0">




But under the conditions described language is not living--it

has only potential life; we have considered only the social, not the
historical, fact.

3) The linguistic sign is arbitrary; language, as defined, would
therefore seem to be a system which, because it depends solely on a
rational principle, is free and can be organized at will. Its social
nature, considered independently, does not definitely rule out this
viewpoint. Doubtless it is not on a purely logical basis that group
psychology operates; one must consider everything that deflects

reason in actual contacts between individuals. But the thing which
keeps language from being a simple convention that can be modi-
fied at the whim of interested parties is not its social nature; it is
rather the action of time combined with the social force. If time
is left out, the linguistic facts are incomplete and no conclusion
is possible.

If we congidered language in time, without the community of
speakers--imagine an isolated individual living for several cen-

turies‹we probably would notice no change; time would not
influence language. Conversely, if we considered the community
of speakers without considering time, we would not see the effect
of the social forces that influence language. To represent the actual
facts, we must then add to our first drawing a sign to indicate
passage of time:

<img src="saussure5.jpeg" height="0" width="0">



Language is no longer free, for time will allow the social forces

at work on it to carry out their effects. This brings us back to the
principle of continuity, which cancels freedom. But continuity
necessarily implies change, varying degrees of shifts in the relation
ship between the signified and the signifier.

(from Saussure's Course in General Linguistics (Phil Library, 1966) pp. 65-78.)