Difference between revisions of "Sexual Difference"

From No Subject - Encyclopedia of Psychoanalysis
Jump to: navigation, search
Line 1: Line 1:
sexual difference                The phrase 'sexual difference', which has come into
+
sexual difference                 
  
prominence in the debate between psychoanalysis and feminism, is not part of
+
The phrase 'sexual difference', which has come into prominence in the debate between psychoanalysis and feminism, is not part of Freud's or Lacan's theoretical vocabulary. Freud speaks only of the anatomical distinction between the sexes and its psychical consequences.<ref> (Freud, 1925d)</ref>
  
Freud's or Lacan's theoretical vocabulary. Freud speaks only of the anatomical
+
Lacan speaks of sexual position and the sexual relationship, and occasionally of the differentiation of the sexes.<ref> (S4, 153)</ref>  However, both Freud and Lacan address the question of sexual difference, and an entry has been included for this term because it brings together an important set of related themes in Lacan's work, and because it constitutes an important focus for feminist approaches to Lacan's work.<ref> (see Brennan, 1989; Gallop, 1982; Grosz, 1990; Mitchell and Rose, 1982)</ref>
  
distinction between the sexes and its psychical consequences (Freud, 1925d);
+
One of the basic presuppositions underlying Freud's work is that just as there are certain physical differences between men and women, so also there are psychical differences. In other words, there are certain psychical characteristics that can be called 'masculine' and others that can be called 'feminine'.
 +
Rather than trying to give any formal defmition of these terms (an impossible task),<ref>  - Freud, 1920a: SE XVIII, 17 l</ref> Freud limits himself to describing how a human subject comes to acquire masculine or feminine psychical characteristics. This is not an instinctual or natural process, but a complex one in which anatomical differences interact with social and psychical factors. The whole process revolves around the [[Castration Complex]], in which the boy fears being deprived of his penis and the girl, assuming that she has already been deprived of hers, develops penis envy.
  
Lacan speaks of sexual position and the sexual relationship, and occasionally
+
Following Freud, Lacan also engages with the problem of how the human infant becomes a sexed subject. For Lacan, masculinity and femininity are not biological essences but [[Symbolic]] positions, and the assumption of one of these two positions is fundamental to the construction of subjectivity; the subject is essentially a sexed subject. 'Man' and '[[Woman]]'            are signifiers that stand for these two subjective positions.<ref>(S20, 34)</ref>
  
of the differentiation of the sexes (S4, 153). However, both Freud and Lacan
+
For both Freud and Lacan, the child is at first ignorant of sexual difference and so cannot take up a sexual position. It is only when the child discovers sexual difference in the [[Castration Complex]] that he can begin to take up a sexual position. Both Freud and Lacan see this process of taking up a sexual position as closely connected with the [[Oedipus Complex]], but they differ on the precise nature of the connection. For Freud, the subject's sexual position is determined by the sex of the parent with whom the subject identifies in the Oedipus complex (if the subject identifies with the father, he takes up a masculine position; identification with the mother entails the assumption of a feminine position).
  
address the question of sexual difference, and an entry has been included for
+
For Lacan, however, the Oedipus complex always involves [[Symbolic]] identification with the Father, and hence Oedipal identification cannot determine sexual position. According to Lacan, then, it is not identification but the subject's relationship with the [[Phallus]] which determines sexual position.
 +
This relationship can either be one of 'having' or 'not having'; men have the [[Symbolic]] phallus, and women don't (or, to be more precise, men are 'not without having it' [ils ne sont pas sans l'avoir]). The assumption of a sexual position is fundamentally a [[Symbolic]] act, and the difference between the sexes can only be conceived of on the [[Symbolic]] plane.<ref> (S4, 153)</ref>
 +
It is insofar as the function of man and [[Woman]] is symbolized, it is insofar as it's literally uprooted from the domain of the [[Imaginary]] and situated in the domain of the [[Symbolic]], that any normal, completed sexual position is realized.<ref> (S3, 177)<.ref>
 +
However, there is no signifier of sexual difference as such which would permit the subject to fully symbolise the function of man and [[Woman]], and hence it is impossible to attain a fully 'normal, finished sexual position'. The subject's sexual identity is thus always a rather precarious matter, a source of perpetual self-questioning. The question of one's own sex ('Am I a man or a [[Woman]]?') is the question which defines [[hysteria]]. The mysterious 'other sex' is always the [[Woman]], for both men and women, and therefore the question of the hysteric ('What is a [[Woman]]?') is the same for both male and female hysterics.<ref> (S3, 178)</ref>
  
this term because it brings together an important set of related themes in
+
Although the anatomy/[[biology]] of the subject plays a part in the question of which sexual position the subject will take up, it is a fundamental axiom in psychoanalytic theory that anatomy does not determine sexual position. There is a rupture between the biological aspect of sexual difference (for example at the level of the chromosomes) which is related to the reproductive function of sexuality, and the unconscious, in which this reproductive function is not represented. Given the non-representation of the reproductive function of sexuality in the unconscious, 'in the psyche there is nothing by which the subject may situate himself as a male or female being'.<ref> (S11, 204)</ref> There is no signifier of sexual difference in the [[Symbolic]] order. The only sexual signifier is the phallus, and there is no 'female' equivalent of this signifier: 'strictly speaking there is no symbolization of [[Woman]]'s sex as such          . . . the phallus is a symbol to which there is no correspondent, no equivalent. It's a matter of a dissymmetry in the signifier'.<ref> (S3, 176)</ref>  Hence the phallus is 'the pivot which completes in both sexes the questioning of their sex by the [[Castration Complex]]'.<ref> (E, 198)</ref>
  
Lacan's work, and because it constitutes            an important focus for feminist
+
It is this fundamental dissymmetry in the signifier which leads to the dissymmetry between the Oedipus complex in men and women. Whereas the male subject desires the parent of the other sex and identifies with the parent of the same sex, the female subject desires the parent of the same sex and 'is required to take the image of the other sex as the basis of its identification'.<ref> (S3, 176)</ref>  'For a [[Woman]] the realization of her sex is not accomplished in the Oedipus complex in a way symmetrical to that of the man's, not by identification with the mother, but on the contrary by identification with the paternal object, which assigns her an extra detour'.<ref>(S3, 172)</ref>
 
+
'This signifying dissymmetry determines the paths down which the Oedipus complex will pass. The two paths make them both pass down the same trail - the trail of castration'.<ref> (S3, 176)</ref>
approaches to Lacan's work (see Brennan, 1989; Gallop, 1982; Grosz, 1990;
+
If, then, there is no symbol for the opposition masculine-feminine as such, the only way to understand sexual difference is in terms of the opposition activity-passivity.<ref> (Sll, 192)</ref>  This polarity is the only way in which the opposition male-female is represented in the psyche, since the biological function of sexuality (reproduction) is not represented.<ref>(Sll, 204)</ref>  This is why the question of what one is to do as a man or a [[Woman]] is a drama which is situated entirely in the field of the Other (Sll, 204), which is to say that the subject can only [[Real]]ise his sexuality on the [[Symbolic]] level.<ref> (S3, 170)</ref>
 
+
In the seminar of 1970-1 Lacan tries to formalise his theory of sexual difference by means of formulae derived from [[Symbolic]] logic. These reappear in the diagram of sexual difference which Lacan presents in the 1972-3 seminar.<ref> (Figurel6, taken from S20, 73)</ref>  The diagram is divided into two sides: on the left, the male side, and on the right, the female side. The formulae of sexuation appear at the top of the diagram. Thus the formulae on the male side are Exæ (= there is at least one x which is not submitted to the phallic function) and Vx¢x (= for all x, the phallic function is valid). The formulae on the female side are Exæ (= there is not one x which is not submitted to the phallic function) and TGx (= for not all x, the phallic function is valid). The last formula illustrates the relationship of [[woman]] (O the logic of the not-all. What is most striking is that the two propositions on each side of the diagram seem to contradict each other: 'each side is defined by both an affirmation and a negation of the phallic function, an inclusion and exclusion of absolute (non-phallic) jouissance'.<ref>(Copjec, 1994: 27)</ref> However, there is no symmetry between the two sides (no sexual relationship); each side represents  a radically different way in which the [[sexual relationship]] can misfire.<ref> (S20, 53-4)</ref>
Mitchell and Rose, 1982).
 
 
 
    One of the basic presuppositions underlying Freud's work is that just as
 
 
 
there are certain physical differences between men and women, so also there
 
 
 
are psychical differences. In other words, there are certain psychical character-
 
 
 
istics that can be called 'masculine' and others that can be called 'feminine'.
 
 
 
Rather than trying to give any formal defmition of these terms (an impossible
 
 
 
task  - Freud, 1920a: SE XVIII, 17 l), Freud limits himself to describing how a
 
 
 
human subject comes to acquire masculine or feminine psychical character-
 
 
 
istics. This is not an instinctual or natural process, but a complex one in which
 
 
 
anatomical differences interact with social and psychical factors. The whole
 
 
 
process revolves around the [[CASTRATION COMPLEX]], in which the boy fears being
 
 
 
deprived of his penis and the girl, assuming that she has already been deprived
 
 
 
of hers, develops penis envy.
 
 
 
      Following Freud, Lacan also engages with the problem of how the human
 
 
 
infant becomes a sexed subject. For Lacan, masculinity and femininity are not
 
 
 
biological essences but [[Symbolic]] positions, and the assumption of one of these
 
 
 
two positions is fundamental to the construction of subjectivity; the subject is
 
 
 
essentially a sexed subject. 'Man' and '[[Woman]]'            are signifiers that stand for
 
 
 
these two subjective positions(S20, 34).
 
 
 
      For both Freud and Lacan, the child is at first ignorant of sexual difference and
 
 
 
  so cannot take up a sexual position. It is only when the child discovers sexual
 
 
 
difference in the [[Castration Complex]] that he can begin to take up a sexual
 
 
 
position. Both Freud and Lacan see this process of taking up a sexual position
 
 
 
  as closely connected with the OEDIPUS COMPLEx, but they differ on the precise
 
 
 
nature of the connection. For Freud, the subject's sexual position is determined
 
 
 
by the sex of the parent with whom the subject identifies in the Oedipus complex
 
 
 
(if the subject identifies with the father, he takes up a masculine position;
 
 
 
identification with the mother entails the assumption of a feminine position).
 
 
 
For Lacan, however, the Oedipus complex always involves [[Symbolic]] identifica-
 
 
 
tion with the Father, and hence Oedipal identification cannot determine sexual
 
 
 
position. According to Lacan, then, it is not identification but the subject's
 
 
 
relationship with the [[Phallus]] which determines sexual position.
 
 
 
      This relationship can either be one of 'having' or 'not having'; men have the
 
 
 
[[Symbolic]] phallus, and women don't (or, to be more precise, men are 'not
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
without having it' [ils ne sont pas sans l'avoir]). The assumption of a sexual
 
 
 
position is fundamentally a [[Symbolic]] act, and the difference between the sexes
 
 
 
can only be conceived of on the [[Symbolic]] plane (S4, 153):
 
 
 
    It is insofar as the function of man and [[Woman]] is symbolized, it is insofar as
 
 
 
    it's literally uprooted from the domain of the [[Imaginary]] and situated in the
 
 
 
    domain of the [[Symbolic]], that any normal, completed sexual position is
 
 
 
    [[Real]]ized.
 
 
 
                                                                                                              (S3, 177)
 
 
 
    However, there is no signifier of sexual difference as such which would
 
 
 
permit the subject to fully symbolise the function of man and [[Woman]], and
 
 
 
hence it is impossible to attain a fully 'normal, finished sexual position'. The
 
 
 
subject's sexual identity is thus always a rather precarious matter, a source of
 
 
 
perpetual self-questioning. The question of one's own sex ('Am I a man or a
 
 
 
[[Woman]]?') is the question which defineS HYSTERIA. The mysterious 'other sex' is
 
 
 
always the [[Woman]], for both men and women, and therefore the question of the
 
 
 
hysteric ('What is a [[Woman]]?') is the same for both male and female hysterics
 
 
 
(S3, 178).
 
 
 
    Although the anatomy/BIOLOGY Of the subject plays a part in the question of
 
 
 
which sexual position the subject will take up, it is a fundamental axiom in
 
 
 
psychoanalytic theory that anatomy does not determine sexual position. There
 
 
 
is a rupture between the biological aspect of sexual difference (for example at
 
 
 
the level of the chromosomes) which is related to the reproductive function of
 
 
 
sexuality, and the unconscious, in which this reproductive function is not
 
 
 
represented. Given the non-representation of the reproductive function of
 
 
 
sexuality in the unconscious, 'in the psyche there is nothing by which the
 
 
 
subject may situate himself as a male or female being' (S11, 204). There is no
 
 
 
signifier of sexual difference in the [[Symbolic]] order. The only sexual signifier is
 
 
 
the phallus, and there is        no 'female' equivalent of this signifier: 'strictly
 
 
 
speaking there is no symbolization of [[Woman]]'s sex as such          . . . the phallus
 
 
 
is a symbol to which there is no correspondent, no equivalent. It's a matter of a
 
 
 
dissymmetry in the signifier' (S3, 176). Hence the phallus is 'the pivot which
 
 
 
completes in both sexes the questioning of their sex by the [[Castration Complex]]'
 
 
 
(E, 198).
 
 
 
    It is this fundamental dissymmetry in the signifier which leads to the
 
 
 
dissymmetry between the Oedipus complex in           men and women. Whereas
 
 
 
the male subject desires the parent of the other sex and identifies with the
 
 
 
parent of the same sex, the female subject desires the parent of the same sex
 
 
 
and 'is required to take the image of the other               sex   as the basis of its
 
 
 
identification' (S3, 176). 'For       a   [[Woman]] the [[Real]]ization of her     sex is not
 
 
 
accomplished in the Oedipus complex in a way symmetrical to that of the
 
 
 
man's, not by identification with the mother, but on the contrary by identifica-
 
 
 
tion with the paternal object, which assigns her an extra detour' (S3, 172).
 
 
 
'This signifying dissymmetry determines the paths down which the Oedipus
 
 
 
complex will pass. The two paths make them both pass down the same trail       -
 
 
 
the trail of castration' (S3, 176).
 
 
 
    If, then, there is no symbol for the opposition masculine-feminine as such,
 
 
 
the only way to understand sexual difference is in terms of the opposition
 
 
 
activity-passivity (Sll, 192). This polarity is the only way in which the
 
 
 
opposition male-female is represented in the psyche, since the biological
 
 
 
function of sexuality (reproduction) is not represented (Sll, 204). This is
 
 
 
why the question of what one is to do as a man or a [[Woman]] is a drama which
 
 
 
is situated entirely in the field of the Other (Sll, 204), which is to say that the
 
 
 
subject can only [[Real]]ise his sexuality on the [[Symbolic]] level (S3, 170).
 
 
 
    In the seminar of 1970-1 Lacan tries to formalise his theory of sexual
 
 
 
difference by means of formulae derived from [[Symbolic]] logic. These reappear
 
 
 
in the diagram of sexual difference which Lacan presents in the 1972-3
 
 
 
seminar (Figurel6, taken from S20, 73). The diagram is divided into two
 
 
 
sides:   on the left, the male side, and on the right, the female side. The
 
 
 
formulae of sexuation appear at the top of the diagram. Thus the formulae
 
 
 
on the male side are Exæ (= there is at least one x which is not submitted to
 
 
 
the phallic function) and Vx¢x (= for all x, the phallic function is valid). The
 
 
 
formulae on the female side are Exæ (= there is not one x which is not
 
 
 
submitted to the phallic function) and TGx (= for not all x, the phallic
 
 
 
function is valid). The last formula illustrates the relationship of [[WOMAN]] (O
 
 
 
the logic of the not-all. What is most striking is that the two propositions on
 
 
 
each side of the diagram seem to contradict each other: 'each side is defined by
 
 
 
both an affirmation and a negation of the phallic function, an inclusion and
 
 
 
exclusion of absolute (non-phallic) jouissance' (Copjec, 1994: 27). However,
 
 
 
there is no symmetry between the two sides (no sexual relationship); each side
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
represents  a radically different way in which the SEXUAL RELATIONSHIP CAD
 
 
 
misfire (S20, 53-4).
 
  
  

Revision as of 16:58, 2 May 2006

sexual difference

The phrase 'sexual difference', which has come into prominence in the debate between psychoanalysis and feminism, is not part of Freud's or Lacan's theoretical vocabulary. Freud speaks only of the anatomical distinction between the sexes and its psychical consequences.[1]

Lacan speaks of sexual position and the sexual relationship, and occasionally of the differentiation of the sexes.[2] However, both Freud and Lacan address the question of sexual difference, and an entry has been included for this term because it brings together an important set of related themes in Lacan's work, and because it constitutes an important focus for feminist approaches to Lacan's work.[3]

One of the basic presuppositions underlying Freud's work is that just as there are certain physical differences between men and women, so also there are psychical differences. In other words, there are certain psychical characteristics that can be called 'masculine' and others that can be called 'feminine'. Rather than trying to give any formal defmition of these terms (an impossible task),[4] Freud limits himself to describing how a human subject comes to acquire masculine or feminine psychical characteristics. This is not an instinctual or natural process, but a complex one in which anatomical differences interact with social and psychical factors. The whole process revolves around the Castration Complex, in which the boy fears being deprived of his penis and the girl, assuming that she has already been deprived of hers, develops penis envy.

Following Freud, Lacan also engages with the problem of how the human infant becomes a sexed subject. For Lacan, masculinity and femininity are not biological essences but Symbolic positions, and the assumption of one of these two positions is fundamental to the construction of subjectivity; the subject is essentially a sexed subject. 'Man' and 'Woman' are signifiers that stand for these two subjective positions.[5]

For both Freud and Lacan, the child is at first ignorant of sexual difference and so cannot take up a sexual position. It is only when the child discovers sexual difference in the Castration Complex that he can begin to take up a sexual position. Both Freud and Lacan see this process of taking up a sexual position as closely connected with the Oedipus Complex, but they differ on the precise nature of the connection. For Freud, the subject's sexual position is determined by the sex of the parent with whom the subject identifies in the Oedipus complex (if the subject identifies with the father, he takes up a masculine position; identification with the mother entails the assumption of a feminine position).

For Lacan, however, the Oedipus complex always involves Symbolic identification with the Father, and hence Oedipal identification cannot determine sexual position. According to Lacan, then, it is not identification but the subject's relationship with the Phallus which determines sexual position. This relationship can either be one of 'having' or 'not having'; men have the Symbolic phallus, and women don't (or, to be more precise, men are 'not without having it' [ils ne sont pas sans l'avoir]). The assumption of a sexual position is fundamentally a Symbolic act, and the difference between the sexes can only be conceived of on the Symbolic plane.[6] It is insofar as the function of man and Woman is symbolized, it is insofar as it's literally uprooted from the domain of the Imaginary and situated in the domain of the Symbolic, that any normal, completed sexual position is realized.Cite error: Closing </ref> missing for <ref> tag

Although the anatomy/biology of the subject plays a part in the question of which sexual position the subject will take up, it is a fundamental axiom in psychoanalytic theory that anatomy does not determine sexual position. There is a rupture between the biological aspect of sexual difference (for example at the level of the chromosomes) which is related to the reproductive function of sexuality, and the unconscious, in which this reproductive function is not represented. Given the non-representation of the reproductive function of sexuality in the unconscious, 'in the psyche there is nothing by which the subject may situate himself as a male or female being'.[7] There is no signifier of sexual difference in the Symbolic order. The only sexual signifier is the phallus, and there is no 'female' equivalent of this signifier: 'strictly speaking there is no symbolization of Woman's sex as such . . . the phallus is a symbol to which there is no correspondent, no equivalent. It's a matter of a dissymmetry in the signifier'.[8] Hence the phallus is 'the pivot which completes in both sexes the questioning of their sex by the Castration Complex'.[9]

It is this fundamental dissymmetry in the signifier which leads to the dissymmetry between the Oedipus complex in men and women. Whereas the male subject desires the parent of the other sex and identifies with the parent of the same sex, the female subject desires the parent of the same sex and 'is required to take the image of the other sex as the basis of its identification'.[10] 'For a Woman the realization of her sex is not accomplished in the Oedipus complex in a way symmetrical to that of the man's, not by identification with the mother, but on the contrary by identification with the paternal object, which assigns her an extra detour'.[11] 'This signifying dissymmetry determines the paths down which the Oedipus complex will pass. The two paths make them both pass down the same trail - the trail of castration'.[12] If, then, there is no symbol for the opposition masculine-feminine as such, the only way to understand sexual difference is in terms of the opposition activity-passivity.[13] This polarity is the only way in which the opposition male-female is represented in the psyche, since the biological function of sexuality (reproduction) is not represented.[14] This is why the question of what one is to do as a man or a Woman is a drama which is situated entirely in the field of the Other (Sll, 204), which is to say that the subject can only Realise his sexuality on the Symbolic level.[15] In the seminar of 1970-1 Lacan tries to formalise his theory of sexual difference by means of formulae derived from Symbolic logic. These reappear in the diagram of sexual difference which Lacan presents in the 1972-3 seminar.[16] The diagram is divided into two sides: on the left, the male side, and on the right, the female side. The formulae of sexuation appear at the top of the diagram. Thus the formulae on the male side are Exæ (= there is at least one x which is not submitted to the phallic function) and Vx¢x (= for all x, the phallic function is valid). The formulae on the female side are Exæ (= there is not one x which is not submitted to the phallic function) and TGx (= for not all x, the phallic function is valid). The last formula illustrates the relationship of woman (O the logic of the not-all. What is most striking is that the two propositions on each side of the diagram seem to contradict each other: 'each side is defined by both an affirmation and a negation of the phallic function, an inclusion and exclusion of absolute (non-phallic) jouissance'.[17] However, there is no symmetry between the two sides (no sexual relationship); each side represents a radically different way in which the sexual relationship can misfire.[18]



== def ==Lacan’s formalization of sexual difference in his famous "formulas of sexuation," presented by means of an idiosyncratic usage of mathematical symbols derived from symbolic logic and set theory, attempts to distill Freud’s efforts to distinguish the girl’s experience of castration from the boy’s. In the first logical moment of masculine sexuation, an exception to the phallic function—Lacan’s term for the interdiction of castration—is posited, which is then followed by a contradictory assertion of the function’s universality. Though abstracted beyond immediate recognition, it is possible to discern here the logic of the Freudian primal father, who lives in the masculine subject’s fantasy as the exception that proves the universal rule of castration. In the first logical moment of feminine castration, in contrast, it is asserted that there are no exceptions to the phallic function. But there then follows the notion that "not-all" elements of the feminine subject, elements Lacan represents with the symbol designating the negation of the universal quantifier, are subject to the rule of castration. This is the background to Lacan’s controversial assertion that women are "pas-toute." Though numerous feminists, including luce irigaray, have attacked this claim as a rationalization for what they see as women’s secondary status within a patriarchal socio-symbolic order, others have argued that the implication of Lacan’s assertion is simply that women, or more precisely feminine subjects, do not avail themselves to categorization. Whereas masculine subjects routinely abstract themselves in such a way that they constitute a whole paradoxically unified by the exception embodied by the primal father fantasy (a masculine subject, in colloquial terms, can be "just one of the guys"), feminine subjects, so it appears, feature an irreducible element of singularity, one resistant to counting, that renders each of them, one might say, a world unto herself. The implications of Lacan’s suggestive and oft-misunderstood theory of sexual difference for feminism and the theory of sexuality have still to find their full elaboration. One thing, however, remains clear. For Lacan, sex emerges as an impasse resulting from the impossibility of representing sexual difference symbolically and therefore of establishing sexual identities. In contrast to the Anglo-American ideology of "gender," then, which upholds the idea that masculinity and femininity are socially preestablished meanings that may never be fully embodied, sex, in the Lacanian view, refers instead to the impossibility of sexual meanings themselves, of the frustration of every attempt to define sexual difference in positive terms, and therefore of the unforgiving resistance with which sexuality necessarily thwarts the ambitions of our conscious intentions.

  1. (Freud, 1925d)
  2. (S4, 153)
  3. (see Brennan, 1989; Gallop, 1982; Grosz, 1990; Mitchell and Rose, 1982)
  4. - Freud, 1920a: SE XVIII, 17 l
  5. (S20, 34)
  6. (S4, 153)
  7. (S11, 204)
  8. (S3, 176)
  9. (E, 198)
  10. (S3, 176)
  11. (S3, 172)
  12. (S3, 176)
  13. (Sll, 192)
  14. (Sll, 204)
  15. (S3, 170)
  16. (Figurel6, taken from S20, 73)
  17. (Copjec, 1994: 27)
  18. (S20, 53-4)