Woman

From No Subject - Encyclopedia of Psychoanalysis
Revision as of 09:16, 26 April 2006 by 64.252.129.62 (talk)
Jump to: navigation, search
  woman (femme)            Freud's account of SEXUAL DIFFERENCE is based on the
  view that there are certain psychical characteristics that can be called 'mascu-
  line' and others that can be called 'feminine', and that these differ from each
  other significantly. However, Freud constantly refuses to give any definition of
  the terms 'masculine' and 'feminine', arguing that they               are foundational

concepts which can be used but not elucidated by psychoanalytic theory

(Freud, 1920a: SE XVIII, 171).

      One feature of this opposition is that the two terms do not function in an

exactly symmetrical way. Masculinity is taken by Freud as the paradigm; he

  asserts that there is only one libido, which is masculine, and that the psychical

development of the girl is at first identical to that of the boy, only diverging at

  a later moment. Femininity is thus that which diverges from the masculine

paradigm, and Freud regards it as a mysterious, unexplored region, a 'dark

continent' (Freud, 1926e: SE XX, 212). The 'riddle of the nature of femininity'

(Freud, 1933a: SE XXII, l 13) comes to preoccupy Freud in his later writings,

  and drives him to ask the famous question, 'What does woman want?' (see

Jones, 1953-7: vol. 2, 468). Masculinity is a self-evident given, femininity is a

  zone of mystery:
      Psychoanalysis does not try to describe what a woman is     - that would be a
      task it could scarcely perform  - but sets about enquiring how she comes into
      being, how a woman develops out of a child with a bisexual disposition.
                                                                             (Freud, 1933a: SE XXII, 116).
      Apart from  a few remarks on the function of the MOTHER in the family

complexes (Lacan, 1938), Lacan's pre-war writings do not engage with the

debate on femininity. The occasional statements on the subject which occur in

Lacan's work in the early 1950s are couched in terms derived from Claude

LÈvi-Strauss; women are seen as objects of exchange which circulate like signs

between kinship groups (see LÈvi-Strauss, 1949b). 'Women in the real order

  serve .  . . as objects for the exchanges required by the elementary structures of

kinship' (E, 207). Lacan argues that it is precisely the fact that woman is

pushed into the position of an exchange object that constitutes the difficulty of

  the feminine position:
      For her, there's something insurmountable, let us say unacceptable, in the
      fact of being placed in the position of an object in the symbolic order, to
       which, on the other hand, she is entirely subjected no less than the man.
                                                                                                               (S2, 262)
   Lacan's analysis of the Dora case makes the same point: what is unacceptable
   for Dora is her position as object of exchange between her father and Herr K
   (see Lacan, 1951a). Being in this position of exchange object means that
   woman 'has    a relation of the second degree to this symbolic order' (S2,
   262; see S4, 95-6).
      In 1956, Lacan takes up the traditional association of HYSTERIA with femi-

ninity, arguing that hysteria is in fact nothing other than the question of

femininity itself, the question which may be phrased 'What is a woman?'.

   This is true for both male and female hysterics (S3, 178). The term 'woman'
   here refers not to some biological essence but to a position in the symbolic
   order; it is synonymous with the term 'feminine position'. Lacan also argues
   that 'there is no symbolisation of woman's sex as such', since there is no
   feminine equivalent to the 'highly prevalent symbol' provided by the phallus
   (S3, 176). This symbolic dissymmetry forces the woman to take the same route
   through the Oedipus complex      as the boy, i.e. to identify with the father.
   However, this is more complex for the woman, since she is required to take
   the image of a member of the other sex as the basis for her identification (S3,
   176).
       Lacan returns to the question of femininity in 1958, in         a paper entitled
   'Guiding remarks for a congress on feminine sexuality' (Lacan, 1958d). In
   this paper he notes the impasses which have beset psychoanalytic discussions
   of feminine sexuality, and argues that woman is the Other for both men and
   women; 'Man here acts as the relay whereby the woman becomes this Other
   for herself as she is this Other for him' (Ec, 732).
       Lacan's most important contributions to the debate on femininity come, like
   Freud's, late in his work. In the seminar of 1972-3, Lacan advances the
   concept of a specifically feminine JOUISSANCE Which goes 'beyond the phal-
   lus' (S20, 69); this jouissance is 'of the order of the infinite', like mystical
   ecstasy (S20, 44). Women may experience this jouissance, but they knoW
   nothing about it (S20, 71). It is also in this seminar that Lacan takes up his
   controversial formula, first advanced in the seminar of 1970-1, 'Woman does
   not exist' (la femme n'existe pas  - Lacan, 1973a: 60), which he here rephrases
   as 'there is no such thing as Woman' (il n'y a pas La femme      - S20, 68). As is
   clear in the original French, what Lacan puts into question is not the noun



'woman', but the definite article which precedes it. In French the definite

article indicates universality, and this is precisely the characteristic that

women lack; women 'do not lend themselves to generalisation, even to

phallocentric generalisation' (Lacan, 1975b). Hence Lacan strikes through

the definite article whenever it precedes the term femme in much the same

way as he strikes through the A to produce the symbol for the barred Other, for

like woman, the Other does not exist (see BAR). To press home the point, Lacan

speaks of woman as 'not-all' (pas-toute; S20, 13); unlike masculinity, which is

a universal function founded upon the phallic exception (castration), woman is

a non-universal which admits of no exception. Woman is compared to truth,

since both partake of the logic of the not-all (there is no such thing as all

women; it is impossible to say 'the whole truth') (Lacan, 1973a: 64).

    Lacan goes on in 1975 to state that 'a woman is a symptom' (Lacan, 1974-5:

seminar of 21 January 1975). More precisely, a woman is a symptom of a man,

in the sense that a woman can only ever enter the psychic economy of men as a

fantasy object (a), the cause of their desire.

    Lacan's remarks   on woman and on feminine sexuality have become the

focus of controversy and debate in feminist theory. Feminists have divided

over whether to see Lacan as an ally or an enemy of the feminist cause. Some

have seen his theories as providing an incisive description of patriarchy and as

a way of challenging fixed concepts of sexual identity (e.g. Mitchell and Rose,

1982). Others have argued that his concept of the symbolic order reinstates

patriarchy as a transhistorical given, and that his privileging of the phallus

simply repeats the alleged misogynies of Freud himself (e.g. Gallop, 1982;

Grosz, 1990). For representative samples of the debate, see Adams and Cowie

(1990) and Brennan (1989). For a Lacanian account of feminine sexuality, see

Leader (1996).


Kid A In Alphabet Land

Kid A In Alphabet Land Wallops Another Wayward Wench - The Wanton Woman!

Wouldn't I Like To Whack You - But Isn't That What You Want! You Fill Out The Lack In Man! You Are The Ideal Partner With Whom The Sexual Relationship Is Finally Realized - Not! Hmph! The Woman Doesn't Exist!