Changes

Jump to: navigation, search
no edit summary
==Abstract==
 The conclusion drawn was that this failure was due to underestimating the depth of Western Christian spiritual foundations, so the accent of subversive activity shifted from politico-economic struggle to "cultural revolution," to the patient intellectual-cultural work of undermining national pride, family, religion, and spiritual commitments, and the spirit of sacrifice for one's country was dismissed as involving the "authoritarian personality"; marital fidelity was supposed to express pathological sexual repression; following Benjamin's motto on how every document of culture is a document of barbarism, the highest achievements of Western culture were denounced for concealing the practices of racism and genocide, and so on. MacDonald devotes many pages to The Authoritarian Personality (1950), a collective project coordinated by Adorno, the purpose of which was, for MacDonald, to make every group affiliation sound as if it were a sign of mental disorder; everything, from patriotism to religion to family-and race-loyally, is disqualified as a sign of a dangerous and defective "authoritarian personality." In addition to ridiculing patriotism and racial identity, the Frankfurt school glorified promiscuity and bohemianhttp://www.nosubject.com/Main_Pagehttp://www.nosubject.com/Main_Page bohemian poverty: "Certainly many of the central attitudes of the largely successful 1960s countercultural revolution find expression in The Authoritarian Personality, including idealizing rebellion against parents, low-investment sexual relationships, and scorn for upward social mobility, social status, family pride, the Christian religion, and patriotism" (CC, p. 194).
==Full Text==
Here is what a<sup> </sup>well-known Slovene Catholic intellectual,<sup> </sup>ex-minister of culture and<sup> </sup>ex-ambassador of Slovenia in<sup> </sup>France<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">in short, an ethically<sup> </sup>corrupted nobody posing as<sup> </sup>a high Christian ethical<sup> </sup>authority<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">wrote apropos Jacques Derrida's<sup> </sup>untimely death, without the<sup> </sup>letters written turning red<sup> </sup>out of shame:
</p><blockquote><i>The<sup> </sup>only weapon is rebellion<sup> </sup>and destruction, as the<sup> </sup>recently deceased apostle Jacques<sup> </sup>Derrida taught us. Wherever<sup> </sup>you see a window,<sup> </sup>throw into it a<sup> </sup>brick. Where there is<sup> </sup>a building, there must<sup> </sup>be a mine. Where<sup> </sup>there is a high-rise<sup> </sup>building, a bin Laden<sup> </sup>should come. Where there<sup> </sup>is any kind of<sup> </sup>institution, law, or link,<sup> </sup>one should find a<sup> </sup>falsification, a "law" of<sup> </sup>the street or of<sup> </sup>the underground.<a href="#fn1" name="cfn1"><sup>1</sup></a></i><p></pblockquote>
</blockquote> Are lines<sup> </sup>like these not an<sup> </sup>indication of the rise<sup> </sup>of a new barbarism<sup> </sup>in today's intellectual life?<sup> </sup>Phenomena Phenomena like the one<sup> </sup>quoted above are not<sup> </sup>limited to marginal countries<sup> </sup>like Slovenia. In the<sup> </sup>homeland of the empire<sup> </sup>itself, theories are emerging<sup> </sup>that, say, explain how<sup> </sup>the Frankfurt school appeared<sup> </sup>on the scene at<sup> </sup>a precise historical moment:<sup> </sup>when the failure of<sup> </sup>the socioeconomic Marxist revolutions<sup> </sup>became apparent. The conclusion<sup> </sup>drawn was that this<sup> </sup>failure was due to<sup> </sup>underestimating the depth of<sup> </sup>Western Christian spiritual foundations,<sup> </sup>so the accent of<sup> </sup>subversive activity shifted from<sup> </sup>politico-economic struggle to "cultural<sup> </sup>revolution," to the patient<sup> </sup>intellectual-cultural work of undermining<sup> </sup>national pride, family, religion,<sup> </sup>and spiritual commitments, and<sup> </sup>the spirit of sacrifice<sup> </sup>for one's country was<sup> </sup>dismissed as involving the<sup> </sup>"authoritarian personality"; marital fidelity<sup> </sup>was supposed to express<sup> </sup>pathological sexual repression; following<sup> </sup>Benjamin's motto on how<sup> </sup>every document of culture<sup> </sup>is a document of<sup> </sup>barbarism, the highest achievements<sup> </sup>of Western culture were<sup> </sup>denounced for concealing the<sup> </sup>practices of racism and<sup> </sup>genocide, and so on.<sup> </sup>The main academic proponent<sup> </sup>of this new barbarism<sup> </sup>is Kevin MacDonald, who,<sup> </sup>in <i>The Culture of Critique</i>, argues that<sup> </sup>certain twentieth-century intellectual movements<sup> </sup>led by Jews have<sup> </sup>changed European societies in<sup> </sup>fundamental ways and destroyed<sup> </sup>the confidence of Western<sup> </sup>man; these movements were<sup> </sup>designed, consciously or unconsciously,<sup> </sup>to advance Jewish interests<sup> </sup>even though they were<sup> </sup>presented to non-Jews as<sup> </sup>universalistic and even utopian.<sup> </sup>One of the most<sup> </sup>consistent ways in which<sup> </sup>Jews have advanced their<sup> </sup>interests has been to<sup> </sup>promote pluralism and diversity<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">but<sup> </sup>only for others. Ever<sup> </sup>since the nineteeth century,<sup> </sup>they have led movements<sup> </sup>that tried to discredit<sup> </sup>the traditional foundations of<sup> </sup>gentile society: patriotism, racial<sup> </sup>loyalty, the Christian basis<sup> </sup>for morality, social homogeneity,<sup> </sup>and sexual restraint. MacDonald<sup> </sup>devotes many pages to<sup> </sup><i>The Authoritarian Personality</i> (1950), a collective<sup> </sup>project coordinated by Adorno,<sup> </sup>the purpose of which<sup> </sup>was, for MacDonald, to<sup> </sup>make every group affiliation<sup> </sup>sound as if it<sup> </sup>were a sign of<sup> </sup>mental disorder; everything, from<sup> </sup>patriotism to religion to<sup> </sup>family<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">and race<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">loyalty, is disqualified<sup> </sup>as a sign of<sup> </sup>a dangerous and defective<sup> </sup>"authoritarian personality." Because drawing<sup> </sup>distinctions between different groups<sup> </sup>is illegitimate, all group<sup> </sup>loyalties<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">even close family ties<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">are<sup> </sup>"prejudice." MacDonald quotes here<sup> </sup>approvingly Christopher Lasch's remark<sup> </sup>that <i>The Authoritarian Personality</i> leads to<sup> </sup>the conclusion that prejudice<sup> </sup>"`could be eradicated only<sup> </sup>by subjecting the American<sup> </sup>people to what amounted<sup> </sup>to collective psychotherapy<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">by treating<sup> </sup>them as inmates of<sup> </sup>an insane asylum.'"<a href="#fn2" name="cfn2"><sup>2</sup></a> However,<sup> </sup>it is precisely the<sup> </sup>kind of group loyalty,<sup> </sup>respect for tradition, and<sup> </sup>consciousness of differences central<sup> </sup>to <i>Jewish</i> identity that,<sup> </sup>according to MacDonald, Horkheimer<sup> </sup>and Adorno described as<sup> </sup>mental illness in gentiles.<sup> </sup>These writers adopted what<sup> </sup>eventually became a favorite<sup> </sup>Soviet tactic against dissidents:<sup> </sup>anyone whose political views<sup> </sup>were different from theirs<sup> </sup>was insane. For these<sup> </sup>Jewish intellectuals, anti-Semitism was<sup> </sup>also a sign of<sup> </sup>mental illness: Christian self-denial<sup> </sup>and especially sexual repression<sup> </sup>caused hatred of Jews.<sup> </sup>The Frankfurt school was<sup> </sup>enthusiastic about psychoanalysis, ac<a></a><a></a>cording<sup> </sup>to which "`oedipal ambivalence<sup> </sup>toward the father and<sup> </sup>anal-sadistic relations in early<sup> </sup>childhood are the anti-Semite's<sup> </sup>irrevocable inheritance'" (<a href="#fn2" name="cfn2"><i>CC</i></a><i>,</i> p.<sup> </sup>145). In addition to<sup> </sup>ridiculing patriotism and racial<sup> </sup>identity, the Frankfurt school<sup> </sup>glorified promiscuity and bohemian<sup> </sup>poverty: "Certainly many of<sup> </sup>the central attitudes of<sup> </sup>the largely successful 1960s<sup> </sup>countercultural revolution find expression<sup> </sup>in <i>The Authoritarian Personality</i>, including idealizing<sup> </sup>rebellion against parents, low-investment<sup> </sup>sexual relationships, and scorn<sup> </sup>for upward social mobility,<sup> </sup>social status, family pride,<sup> </sup>the Christian religion, and<sup> </sup>patriotism" (<a href="#fn2" name="cfn2"><i>CC</i></a><i>,</i> p. 194).<sup> </sup>Although he came later,<sup> </sup>Derrida followed the same<sup> </sup>tradition when he wrote:<sup> </sup>"`The idea behind deconstruction<sup> </sup>is to deconstruct the<sup> </sup>workings of strong nation-states<sup> </sup>with powerful immigration policies,<sup> </sup>to deconstruct the rhetoric<sup> </sup>of nationalism, the politics<sup> </sup>of place, the metaphysics<sup> </sup>of native land and<sup> </sup>native tongue.... The idea<sup> </sup>is to disarm the<sup> </sup>bombs... of identity that<sup> </sup>nation-states build to defend<sup> </sup>themselves against the stranger,<sup> </sup>against Jews and Arabs<sup> </sup>and immigrants'" (<a href="#fn2" name="cfn2"><i>CC</i></a><i>,</i> p.<sup> </sup>201). As MacDonald puts<sup> </sup>it, <i>"Viewed at its most abstract level, a fundamental agenda is thus to influence the European-derived peoples of the United States to view concern about their own </i><i>demographic and cultural eclipse as irrational and as an indication of psychopathology"</i> (<a href="#fn2" name="cfn2"><i>CC</i></a><i>,</i> p.<sup> </sup>195). This project has<sup> </sup>been successful; anyone opposed<sup> </sup>to the displacement of<sup> </sup>whites is routinely treated<sup> </sup>as a mentally unhinged<sup> </sup>hatemonger, and whenever whites<sup> </sup>defend their group interests<sup> </sup>they are described as<sup> </sup>psychologically inadequate<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">with, of course,<sup> </sup>the silent exception of<sup> </sup>the Jews themselves: "the<sup> </sup>ideology that ethnocentrism was<sup> </sup>a form of psychopathology<sup> </sup>was promulgated by a<sup> </sup>group that over its<sup> </sup>long history had arguably<sup> </sup>been the most ethnocentric<sup> </sup>group among all the<sup> </sup>cultures of the world"<sup> </sup>(<a href="#fn2" name="cfn2"><i>CC</i></a><i>,</i> p. 232). We<sup> </sup>should have no illusions<sup> </sup>here. Measured by the<sup> </sup>standards of the great<sup> </sup>Enlightenment tradition, we are<sup> </sup>effectively dealing with something<sup> </sup>for which the best<sup> </sup>designation is the old<sup> </sup>orthodox Marxist term for<sup> </sup>"bourgeois irrationalists": <i>the self-destruction of reason</i>. The<sup> </sup>only thing to bear<sup> </sup>in mind is that<sup> </sup>this new barbarism is<sup> </sup>a strictly postmodern phenomenon,<sup> </sup>the obverse of the<sup> </sup>highly reflexive self-ironical attitude<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">no<sup> </sup>wonder that, reading authors<sup> </sup>like MacDonald, one often<sup> </sup>cannot decide if one<sup> </sup>is reading a satire<sup> </sup>or a "serious" line<sup> </sup>of argumentation.<sup> </sup><p></p>
<p>&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;But the saddest<sup> </sup>surprise of them all<sup> </sup>is to see some<sup> </sup>of the theoretical descendants<sup> </sup>of those who are<sup> </sup>amalgamated by MacDonald into<sup> </sup>the same Jewish plot<sup> </sup>with Derrida<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">some late representatives<sup> </sup>of the Frankfurt school<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">propose<sup> </sup>a kind of symmetrical<sup> </sup>reversal of the same<sup> </sup>story, which ends up<sup> </sup>in no less atrocious<sup> </sup>slander. Instead of being<sup> </sup>castigated as an agent<sup> </sup>of the Jewish plot,<sup> </sup>Derrida is here, together<sup> </sup>with Baudrillard and others,<sup> </sup>thrown into the "postmodern"<sup> </sup>melting pot that, so<sup> </sup>the story goes, opens<sup> </sup>up the way for<sup> </sup>proto-Fascist irrationalism, if not<sup> </sup>directly providing the intellectual<sup> </sup>background for Holocaust denial.<sup> </sup>This brutal intolerance, which<sup> </sup>masks as high moral<sup> </sup>concern, found its latest<sup> </sup>exponent in Richard Wolin,<sup> </sup>whose <i>The Seduction of Unreason</i> is a<sup> </sup>worthy successor to Lukács's<sup> </sup>most Stalinist work, the<sup> </sup>infamous <i>Die Zerstörung der Vernunft</i> from the<sup> </sup>early 1950s. Wolin bombastically<sup> </sup>locates me, together with<sup> </sup>Baudrillard, among those who<sup> </sup>claimed that the U.S.<sup> </sup>got what it deserved<sup> </sup>on 9/11:
</p><blockquote><i>Traditionally, dystopian<sup> </sup>views of America have<sup> </sup>been the stock-in-trade of<sup> </sup>counterrevolutionary writers such as<sup> </sup>Maistre, Arthur de Gobineau,<sup> </sup>and Oswald Spengler. More<sup> </sup>recently, they have made<sup> </sup>inroads among champions of<sup> </sup>the postmodern left, such<sup> </sup>as Jean Baudrillard and<sup> </sup>Slavoj <img src="/ucp-entities/Zcaron.gif" alt="&amp;Zcaron;" align="bottom" border="0">i<img src="/ucp-entities/zcaron.gif" alt="&amp;zcaron;" align="bottom" border="0">ek. In their<sup> </sup>theories, America represents the<sup> </sup>epitome of a postmodern,<sup> </sup>technological Moloch: a land<sup> </sup>devoid of history and<sup> </sup>tradition in which the<sup> </sup>seductions and illusions of<sup> </sup>a media-dominated mass culture<sup> </sup>have attained unchallenged hegemony.<sup> </sup>The postmodernists allege that<sup> </sup>the traditional orientations of<sup> </sup>family, community, and politics<sup> </sup>have ceded to the<sup> </sup>febrile delusions of "hyperreality."<sup> </sup>Today, we experience the<sup> </sup>reign of "simulacra": media-generated<sup> </sup>copies, shorn of originals,<sup> </sup>that circulate autonomously. This<sup> </sup>attitude helps explain the<sup> </sup>enthusiasm with which Baudrillard<sup> </sup>greeted the September 11<sup> </sup>attacks: a "dream come<sup> </sup>true."<a href="#fn3" name="cfn3"><sup>3</sup></a></i><p></p>
</blockquote>
De Maistre, Gobineau,<sup> </sup>Spengler, Baudrillard, <img src="/ucp-entities/Zcaron.gif" alt="&amp;Zcaron;" align="bottom" border="0">i<img src="/ucp-entities/zcaron.gif" alt="&amp;zcaron;" align="bottom" border="0">ek. Now<sup> </sup>I know where I<sup> </sup>belong: among the proto-Fascist<sup> </sup>irrationalists. At least I<sup> </sup>am here also in<sup> </sup>a good company, with<sup> </sup>people like Nietzsche and<sup> </sup>Adorno.<a href="#fn4" name="cfn4"><sup>4</sup></a> Wolin is at<sup> </sup>his lowest when he<sup> </sup>"observes" how I report<sup> </sup>on the 9/11 events<sup> </sup>as if I am<sup> </sup>describing just another mediatic<sup> </sup>spectacle, with no moral<sup> </sup>judgments implied. As a<sup> </sup>"proof," Wolin quotes a<sup> </sup>line from my 9/11<sup> </sup>book: "`America got what<sup> </sup>it fantasized about' ...<sup> </sup>which, <img src="/ucp-entities/Zcaron.gif" alt="&amp;Zcaron;" align="bottom" border="0">i<img src="/ucp-entities/zcaron.gif" alt="&amp;zcaron;" align="bottom" border="0">ek insinuates, ...<sup> </sup>is merely another way<sup> </sup>of saying that <i>America got what it had coming.</i>"<a href="#fn5" name="cfn5"><sup>5</sup></a><sup> </sup>This line of argumentation<sup> </sup>is a simple empirical<sup> </sup>lie if there ever<sup> </sup>was one. First, I<sup> </sup>do not claim that<sup> </sup>the U.S. got what<sup> </sup>it deserved, but what<sup> </sup>it "fantasized about," making<sup> </sup>it clear that when<sup> </sup>one gets what one<sup> </sup>fantasizes about, one ends<sup> </sup>up in a nightmare;<sup> </sup>second, and much more<sup> </sup>important, a little bit<sup> </sup>later, I explicitly reject<sup> </sup>the leftist <i>Schadenfreude</i>:
<blockquote><i>The<sup> </sup>American patriotic narrative<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">the innocence<sup> </sup>under siege, the surge<sup> </sup>of patriotic pride<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">is, of<sup> </sup>course, vain; however, is<sup> </sup>the Leftist narrative (with<sup> </sup>its <i>Schadenfreude</i>: the USA<sup> </sup>got what it deserved,<sup> </sup>what it had been<sup> </sup>doing to others for<sup> </sup>decades) really any better?<sup> </sup>The predominant reaction of<sup> </sup>European<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">but also American<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">Leftists was<sup> </sup>nothing less than scandalous:<sup> </sup>all imaginable stupidities were<sup> </sup>said and written, up<sup> </sup>to the "feminist" point<sup> </sup>that the WTC towers<sup> </sup>were two phallic symbols,<sup> </sup>waiting to be destroyed<sup> </sup>("castrated"). Was there not<sup> </sup>something petty and miserable<sup> </sup>in the mathematics reminding<sup> </sup>us of Holocaust revisionism<sup> </sup>(what are the 3,000<sup> </sup>dead against millions in<sup> </sup>Rwanda, Kongo, etc.)? And<sup> </sup>what about the fact<sup> </sup>that the CIA (co-)created<sup> </sup>Taliban and Bin Laden,<sup> </sup>financing and helping them<sup> </sup>to fight the Soviets<sup> </sup>in Afghanistan? Why was<sup> </sup>this fact quoted as<sup> </sup>an argument against attacking<sup> </sup>them? Would it not<sup> </sup>be much more logical<sup> </sup>to claim that it<sup> </sup>is precisely America's duty<sup> </sup>to rid us of<sup> </sup>the monster it created?<sup> </sup>The moment we think<sup> </sup>in the terms of<sup> </sup>"Yes, the WTC collapse<sup> </sup>was a tragedy, but<sup> </sup>we should not fully<sup> </sup>solidarize with the victims,<sup> </sup>since this would mean<sup> </sup>supporting US imperialism," the<sup> </sup>ethical catastrophe is already<sup> </sup>here: the only appropriate<sup> </sup>stance is unconditional solidarity<sup> </sup>with <i>all</i> victims. The<sup> </sup>ethical stance proper is<sup> </sup>here replaced by the<sup> </sup>moralizing mathematics of guilt<sup> </sup>and horror, which misses<sup> </sup>the key point: the<sup> </sup>terrifying death of each<sup> </sup>individual is absolute and<sup> </sup>incomparable. In short, let<sup> </sup>us conduct a simple<sup> </sup>mental experiment: if you<sup> </sup>detect in yourself any<sup> </sup>reluctance to empathize fully<sup> </sup>with the victims of<sup> </sup>the WTC collapse, if<sup> </sup>you feel the urge<sup> </sup>to qualify your empathy<sup> </sup>with "Yes, but what<sup> </sup>about the millions who<sup> </sup>suffer in Africa... ,"<sup> </sup>you are not demonstrating<sup> </sup>your Third World sympathies,<sup> </sup>but merely the <i>mauvaise foi</i><sup> </sup>which bears witness to<sup> </sup>your implicit patronizing racist<sup> </sup>attitude towards Third World<sup> </sup>victims.<a href="#fn6" name="cfn6"><sup>6</sup></a></i><p></p>
</blockquote>
Perhaps, after finding<sup> </sup>myself, together with Derrida,<sup> </sup>in the same boat<sup> </sup>with those slandered by<sup> </sup>the moralizing hypocrites who<sup> </sup>effectively manipulate the memory<sup> </sup>of the 9/11 victims<sup> </sup>in order to score<sup> </sup>cheap "theoretical" points, the<sup> </sup>time has come to<sup> </sup>draw the balance of<sup> </sup>my relations with Derrida,<sup> </sup>in a belated gesture<sup> </sup>of solidarity. Having written<sup> </sup>many pages in which<sup> </sup>I struggle with Derrida's<sup> </sup>work, now<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">when the Derridean<sup> </sup>fashion is fading away<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">it<sup> </sup>is perhaps the moment<sup> </sup>to honor his memory<sup> </sup>by pointing out the<sup> </sup>proximity of the topic<sup> </sup>of my work to<sup> </sup>what Derrida called <i>différance</i>,<sup> </sup>this neologism whose very<sup> </sup>notoriety obfuscates its unheard-of<sup> </sup>materialist potential.<sup> </sup><p></p>
<p>&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;In the last<sup> </sup>two decades of his<sup> </sup>thought, Derrida emphasized that,<sup> </sup>the more radical a<sup> </sup>deconstruction is, the more<sup> </sup>it has to rely<sup> </sup>on its inherent "undeconstructible"<sup> </sup>condition of deconstruction, the<sup> </sup>messianic promise of justice.<sup> </sup>This promise is the<sup> </sup>true Derridean object of<sup> </sup><i>belief,</i> and the ultimate<sup> </sup>ethical axiom of Derrida<sup> </sup>is that this belief<sup> </sup>is irreducible, "undeconstructible." Derrida<sup> </sup>can thus indulge in<sup> </sup>all kinds of paradoxes,<sup> </sup>claiming, among other things,<sup> </sup>in his reflections on<sup> </sup>prayer, not only that<sup> </sup>atheists also do pray<sup> </sup>but that, today, it<sup> </sup>is perhaps <i>only atheists who truly pray.</i> Precisely<sup> </sup>by refusing to address<sup> </sup>God as a positive<sup> </sup>entity, they silently address<sup> </sup>the pure messianic Otherness.<a href="#fn7" name="cfn7"><sup>7</sup></a><sup> </sup>It is here that<sup> </sup>one should emphasize the<sup> </sup>gap that separates Derrida<sup> </sup>from the Hegelian tradition:<sup> </sup>
</p><blockquote><i>It would be too<sup> </sup>easy to show that,<sup> </sup>measured by the failure<sup> </sup>to establish liberal democracy,<sup> </sup>the gap between fact<sup> </sup>and ideal essence does<sup> </sup>not show up only<sup> </sup>in ... so-called primitive<sup> </sup>forms of government, theocracy,<sup> </sup>and military dictatorship.... But<sup> </sup>this failure and this<sup> </sup>gap also characterize, <i>a priori</i><sup> </sup>and by definition, <i>all</i><sup> </sup>democracies, including the oldest<sup> </sup>and most stable of<sup> </sup>so-called Western democracies. At<sup> </sup>stake here is the<sup> </sup>very concept of democracy<sup> </sup>as concept of a<sup> </sup>promise that can only<sup> </sup>arise in such a<sup> </sup><i>diastema</i> (failure, inadequation, disjunction,<sup> </sup>disadjustment, being "out of<sup> </sup>joint"). That is why<sup> </sup>we always propose to<sup> </sup>speak of a democracy<sup> </sup><i>to come</i>, not of a<sup> </sup><i>future</i> democracy in the<sup> </sup>future present, not even<sup> </sup>of a regulating idea,<sup> </sup>in the Kantian sense,<sup> </sup>or of a utopia<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">at<sup> </sup>least to the extent<sup> </sup>that their inaccessibility would<sup> </sup>still retain the temporal<sup> </sup>form of a <i>future present</i>,<sup> </sup>of a future modality<sup> </sup>of the <i>living present</i>.<a href="#fn8" name="cfn8"><sup>8</sup></a></i><p></p>
</blockquote>
Here<sup> </sup>we get the difference<sup> </sup>between Hegel and Derrida<sup> </sup>at its purest. Derrida<sup> </sup>accepts Hegel's fundamental lesson<sup> </sup>that one cannot assert<sup> </sup>the innocent ideal against<sup> </sup>its distorted realization. This<sup> </sup>holds not only for<sup> </sup>democracy but also for<sup> </sup>religion. The gap that<sup> </sup>separates the ideal concept<sup> </sup>from its actualization is<sup> </sup>already inherent to the<sup> </sup>concept itself. In the<sup> </sup>same way that Derrida<sup> </sup>claims that "God already<sup> </sup>contradicts himself," that any<sup> </sup>positive conceptual determination of<sup> </sup>the divine as a<sup> </sup>pure messianic promise already<sup> </sup>betrays it, one should<sup> </sup>also say that democracy<sup> </sup>already contradicts itself. It<sup> </sup>is also against this<sup> </sup>background that Derrida elaborates<sup> </sup>the mutual implication of<sup> </sup>religion and radical evil.<sup> </sup>Radical evil (politically: "totalitarianism")<sup> </sup>emerges when religious faith<sup> </sup>or reason (or democracy<sup> </sup>itself) is posited in<sup> </sup>the mode of future<sup> </sup>present. However, against Hegel,<sup> </sup>Derrida insists on the<sup> </sup>irreducible excess in the<sup> </sup>ideal concept that cannot<sup> </sup>be reduced to the<sup> </sup>dialectic between ideal and<sup> </sup>its actualization: the messianic<sup> </sup>structure of "to come,"<sup> </sup>the excess of an<sup> </sup>abyss that cannot ever<sup> </sup>be actualized in its<sup> </sup>determinate content. Hegel's own<sup> </sup>position is here more<sup> </sup>intricate than it may<sup> </sup>appear: his point is<sup> </sup>not that, through gradual<sup> </sup>dialectical progress, one can<sup> </sup>master the gap between<sup> </sup>concept and its actualization<sup> </sup>and achieve the concept's<sup> </sup>full self-transparency ("Absolute Knowledge").<sup> </sup>Rather, to put it<sup> </sup>in speculative terms, his<sup> </sup>point is to assert<sup> </sup>a "pure" contradiction that<sup> </sup>is no longer the<sup> </sup>contradiction between the "undeconstructible"<sup> </sup>pure Otherness and its<sup> </sup>failed actualizations/determinations, but the<sup> </sup>thoroughly immanent "contradiction" that<sup> </sup>precedes any Otherness. Actualizations<sup> </sup>and/or conceptual determinations are<sup> </sup>not traces of the<sup> </sup>"undeconstructible" divine Otherness, but<sup> </sup><i>just traces</i> marking their in-between.<sup> </sup>Or, to put it<sup> </sup>in yet another way,<sup> </sup>in a kind of<sup> </sup>inverted phenomenological <i>epoche</i>, Derrida<sup> </sup>reduces Otherness to the<sup> </sup>"to come" of a<sup> </sup>pure potentiality, thoroughly deontologizing<sup> </sup>it, bracketing its positive<sup> </sup>content, so that all<sup> </sup>that remains is the<sup> </sup>specter of a promise;<sup> </sup>and what if the<sup> </sup>next step is to<sup> </sup>drop this minimal specter<sup> </sup>of Otherness itself, so<sup> </sup>that all that remains<sup> </sup>is the rupture, the<sup> </sup>gap as such that<sup> </sup>prevents entities from reaching<sup> </sup>their self-identity?<a href="#fn9" name="cfn9"><sup>9</sup></a> Recall the<sup> </sup>old reproach of the<sup> </sup>French Communist philosophers to<sup> </sup>Sartre's existentialism: Sartre threw<sup> </sup>away the entire content<sup> </sup>of the bourgeois subject,<sup> </sup>maintaining only its pure<sup> </sup>form, and the next<sup> </sup>step is to throw<sup> </sup>away this form itself<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">is<sup> </sup>it not that, <i>mutatis mutandis</i>,<sup> </sup>Derrida threw away all<sup> </sup>positive ontological content of<sup> </sup>messianism, retaining nothing but<sup> </sup>the pure form of<sup> </sup>the messianic promise, and<sup> </sup>the next step is<sup> </sup>to throw away this<sup> </sup>form itself? And, again,<sup> </sup>is this not also<sup> </sup>the passage from Judaism<sup> </sup>to Christianity? Judaism reduces<sup> </sup>the promise of another<sup> </sup>life to a pure<sup> </sup>Otherness, a messianic promise<sup> </sup>that will never become<sup> </sup>fully present and actualized<sup> </sup>(the Messiah is always<sup> </sup>"to come"), while Christianity,<sup> </sup>far from claiming full<sup> </sup>realization of the promise,<sup> </sup>accomplishes something far more<sup> </sup>uncanny: the Messiah <i>is here,</i><sup> </sup>he <i>has</i> arrived, the<sup> </sup>final Event already took<sup> </sup>place, <i>and yet the gap (the gap that sustained the messianic promise) remains.</i> One is<sup> </sup>almost tempted to propose<sup> </sup>here a return to<sup> </sup>the earlier Derrida of<sup> </sup><i>différance</i>: what if (as,<sup> </sup>among others, Ernesto Laclau<sup> </sup>has already proposed)<a href="#fn10" name="cfn10"><sup>10</sup></a> Derrida's<sup> </sup>turn to the "postsecular"<sup> </sup>messianism is not a<sup> </sup>necessary outcome of his<sup> </sup>initial "deconstructionist" impetus? What<sup> </sup>if the idea of<sup> </sup>infinite messianic justice that<sup> </sup>operates in an indefinite<sup> </sup>suspension, always to come,<sup> </sup>as the "undeconstructible" horizon<sup> </sup>of deconstruction, already obfuscates<sup> </sup>the "pure" <i>différance</i>, the<sup> </sup>pure gap that differs<sup> </sup>an entity from itself?<sup> </sup>Is it not possible<sup> </sup>to think this pure<sup> </sup>in-between prior to any<sup> </sup>notion of messianic justice?<sup> </sup>Derrida acts as if<sup> </sup>the choice is between<sup> </sup>the positive ontoethics, the<sup> </sup>gesture of transcending the<sup> </sup>existing order towards another<sup> </sup>higher positive Order, and<sup> </sup>the pure promise of<sup> </sup>spectral Otherness. However, what<sup> </sup>if we drop this<sup> </sup>reference to Otherness altogether?<sup> </sup><p></p>
<p>&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;Perhaps<sup> </sup>this brings us to<sup> </sup>the limits of the<sup> </sup>Derridean deconstruction of metaphysics.<sup> </sup>Three thinkers as different<sup> </sup>as Nietzsche, Heidegger, and<sup> </sup>Derrida all conceive their<sup> </sup>own age as that<sup> </sup>of the critical turning<sup> </sup>point of metaphysics. In<sup> </sup>their (our) time, metaphysics<sup> </sup>has exhausted its potentials,<sup> </sup>and the thinker's duty<sup> </sup>is to prepare the<sup> </sup>ground for a new,<sup> </sup>postmetaphysical thinking. More generally,<sup> </sup>the entire Judeo-Christian history,<sup> </sup>up to our postmodernity,<sup> </sup>is determined by what<sup> </sup>one is tempted to<sup> </sup>call the Hölderlin paradigm,<sup> </sup>which was first articulated<sup> </sup>by Augustine in his<sup> </sup><i>City of God:</i> "Where the danger<sup> </sup>is grows also what<sup> </sup>can save us" ("Wo<sup> </sup>aber Gefahr ist weachst<sup> </sup>das Rettende auch"). The<sup> </sup>present moment appears as<sup> </sup>the lowest point in<sup> </sup>the long process of<sup> </sup>historical decadence (the flight<sup> </sup>of Gods, alienation, and<sup> </sup>so on), but the<sup> </sup>danger of the catastrophic<sup> </sup>loss of the essential<sup> </sup>dimension of being-human also<sup> </sup>opens up the possibility<sup> </sup>of a reversal <i>(Kehre)</i><img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">proletarian<sup> </sup>revolution, the arrival of<sup> </sup>new gods (which, according<sup> </sup>to the late Heidegger,<sup> </sup>can only save us),<sup> </sup>and so on. Are<sup> </sup>we able to imagine<sup> </sup>a "pagan" <i>nonhistorical</i> universe,<sup> </sup>a universe thoroughly outside<sup> </sup>this paradigm, a universe<sup> </sup>in which (historical) time<sup> </sup>just flows with no<sup> </sup>teleological curvature, in which<sup> </sup>the idea of a<sup> </sup>dangerous moment of decision<sup> </sup>(Benjamin's <i>Jetzt-Zeit</i>), out of<sup> </sup>which a "bright future"<sup> </sup>which will redeem the<sup> </sup>past itself can emerge,<sup> </sup>is simply meaningless?<sup> </sup></p>
<p>&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;Although this<sup> </sup>Hölderlin paradigm is usually<sup> </sup>identified with Christianity, Christianity,<sup> </sup>at its most radical,<sup> <a></a><a></a></sup>nonetheless seems to give<sup> </sup>a unique twist to<sup> </sup>it: everything that has<sup> </sup>to happen <i>already happened;</i> there<sup> </sup>is nothing to wait<sup> </sup>for; we do not<sup> </sup>have to wait for<sup> </sup>the Event, for the<sup> </sup>arrival of the Messiah;<sup> </sup>the Messiah has already<sup> </sup>arrived; the Event already<sup> </sup>took place; we live<sup> </sup>in its aftermath. This<sup> </sup>basic attitude of historical<sup> </sup>closure is also the<sup> </sup>message of Hegel, of<sup> </sup>his dictum that the<sup> </sup>owl of Minerva takes<sup> </sup>off in the twilight<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">and<sup> </sup>what is difficult, but<sup> </sup>crucial, to grasp is<sup> </sup>how this stance, far<sup> </sup>from condemning us to<sup> </sup>passive reflection, opens up<sup> </sup>the space for active<sup> </sup>intervention. And does the<sup> </sup>same not go for<sup> </sup>Kierkegaard who, in spite<sup> </sup>of his standard rumblings<sup> </sup>against the mass society<sup> </sup>of the "present age,"<sup> </sup>also does not seem<sup> </sup>to rely on the<sup> </sup>Hölderlin paradigm of historicality<sup> </sup>(and on the <i>hubris</i><sup> </sup>in the self-perception of<sup> </sup>the thinker that such<sup> </sup>a view involves)<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">there is<sup> </sup>nothing really exceptional about<sup> </sup>our age; if anything,<sup> </sup>we live in ordinary<sup> </sup>and noninteresting times?<sup> </sup></p><hr align="center" noshade="noshade" width="60">
<p>&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;What, then,<sup> </sup>would be this <i>différance</i><sup> </sup>that precedes the ethical<sup> </sup>commitment to the abyss<sup> </sup>of Otherness? On the<sup> </sup>southern side of the<sup> </sup>demilitarized zone in Korea,<sup> </sup>there is a unique<sup> </sup>visitor's site: a theater<sup> </sup>building with a large<sup> </sup>screenlike window in front,<sup> </sup>opening up onto the<sup> </sup>North. The spectacle people<sup> </sup>observe when they take<sup> </sup>seats and look through<sup> </sup>the window is reality<sup> </sup>itself (or, rather, a<sup> </sup>kind of "desert of<sup> </sup>the real"): the barren<sup> </sup>demilitarized zone with walls,<sup> </sup>and so on, and,<sup> </sup>beyond, a glimpse of<sup> </sup>North Korea. (As if<sup> </sup>to comply with the<sup> </sup>fiction, North Korea has<sup> </sup>built in front of<sup> </sup>this theater a fake,<sup> </sup>a model village with<sup> </sup>beautiful houses; in the<sup> </sup>evening, the lights in<sup> </sup>all the houses are<sup> </sup>turned on at the<sup> </sup>same time, although nobody<sup> </sup>lives in them.) Is<sup> </sup>this not a pure<sup> </sup>case of the symbolic<sup> </sup>efficiency of the frame<sup> </sup>as such? A barren<sup> </sup>zone is given a<sup> </sup>fantasmatic status, elevated into<sup> </sup>a spectacle, solely by<sup> </sup>being enframed. Nothing substantially<sup> </sup>changes here; it is<sup> </sup>merely that, viewed through<sup> </sup>the frame, reality turns<sup> </sup>into <i>its own appearance</i>. A supreme<sup> </sup>case of such an<sup> </sup>ontological comedy occurred in<sup> </sup>December 2001 in Buenos<sup> </sup>Aires, when Argentinians took<sup> </sup>to the streets to<sup> </sup>protest against their government<sup> </sup>and, especially, against Cavallo,<sup> </sup>the economy minister. When<sup> </sup>the crowd gathered around<sup> </sup>Cavallo's building, threatening to<sup> </sup>storm it, he escaped<sup> </sup>wearing a mask of<sup> </sup>himself (sold in disguise<sup> </sup>shops so that people<sup> </sup>could mock him by<sup> </sup>wearing his mask). It<sup> </sup>thus seems that at<sup> </sup>least Cavallo did learn<sup> </sup>something from the widely<sup> </sup>spread Lacanian movement in<sup> </sup>Argentina<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">the fact that <i>a thing is its own best mask</i>.<sup> </sup>What one encounters in<sup> </sup>tautology is thus pure<sup> </sup>difference, not the difference<sup> </sup>between the element and<sup> </sup>other elements, but how<sup> </sup>the element is different<sup> </sup>from itself.<sup> </sup></p>
<p>&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;The fundamental lesson<sup> </sup>of Hegel is that<sup> </sup>the key ontological problem<sup> </sup>is not that of<sup> </sup>reality but that of<sup> </sup>appearance: not, Are we<sup> </sup>condemned to the interminable<sup> </sup>play of appearances, or<sup> </sup>can we penetrate through<sup> </sup>their veil to the<sup> </sup>underlying true reality? but,<sup> </sup>How could<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">in the middle<sup> </sup>of flat, stupid reality,<sup> </sup>which is <i>just there</i><img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">something like<sup> </sup>appearance emerge? The minimal<sup> </sup>ontology is therefore that<sup> </sup>of the Möbius strip,<sup> </sup>of the curved space<sup> </sup>that is bent onto<sup> </sup>itself; all that has<sup> </sup>to intervene into the<sup> </sup>Real is an empty<sup> </sup>frame so that the<sup> </sup>same things we saw<sup> </sup>"directly" before are now<sup> </sup>seen through the frame.<sup> </sup>A certain surplus-effect is<sup> </sup>thus generated, which cannot<sup> </sup>simply be cancelled through<sup> </sup>demystification. It is not<sup> </sup>enough to display the<sup> </sup>mechanism behind the frame;<sup> </sup>the stage-effect within the<sup> </sup>frame becomes autonomous. How<sup> </sup>is this possible? There<sup> </sup>is only one conclusion<sup> </sup>that can account for<sup> </sup>this gap: there is<sup> </sup>no "neutral" reality within<sup> </sup>which gaps occur, within<sup> </sup>which frames isolate domains<sup> </sup>of appearances. Every field<sup> </sup>of "reality" (every "world")<sup> </sup>is always already enframed,<sup> </sup>seen through an invisible<sup> </sup>frame. However, the parallax<sup> </sup>of the two frames<sup> </sup>is not symmetrical, composed<sup> </sup>of two incompatible perspectives<sup> </sup>on the same <i>x:</i><sup> </sup>there is an irreducible<sup> </sup>asymmetry between the two<sup> </sup>perspectives, a minimal reflexive<sup> </sup>twist. We do not<sup> </sup>have two perspectives; we<sup> </sup>have a perspective and<sup> </sup>what eludes it, and<sup> </sup>the other perspective fills<sup> </sup>in this void of<sup> </sup>what we could not<sup> </sup>see from the first<sup> </sup>perspective.<sup> </sup></p>
<p>&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;One of the minimal<sup> </sup>definitions of a modernist<sup> </sup>painting concerns the function<sup> </sup>of its frame. The<sup> </sup>frame of the painting<sup> </sup>in front of us<sup> </sup>is not its true<sup> </sup>frame; there is another,<sup> </sup>invisible frame, the frame<sup> </sup>implied by the structure<sup> </sup>of the painting, the<sup> </sup>frame that enframes our<sup> </sup>perception of the painting,<sup> </sup>and these two frames<sup> </sup>by definition never overlap.<sup> </sup>There is an invisible<sup> </sup>gap separating them. The<sup> </sup>pivotal content of the<sup> </sup>painting is not rendered<sup> </sup>in its visible part<sup> </sup>but is located in<sup> </sup>this dis-location of the<sup> </sup>two frames, in the<sup> </sup>gap that separates them.<sup> </sup>This dimension in-between-the-two-frames is<sup> </sup>obvious in Kazimir Malevich<sup> </sup>(what is his <i>Black Square on White Surface</i><sup> </sup>if not the minimal<sup> </sup>marking of the distance<sup> </sup>between the two frames?),<sup> </sup>in Edward Hopper (recall<sup> </sup>his lone figures in<sup> </sup>office buildings or diners<sup> </sup>at night, where it<sup> </sup>seems as if the<sup> </sup>picture's frame has to<sup> </sup>be redoubled with another<sup> </sup>window frame, or, in<sup> </sup>the portraits of his<sup> </sup>wife close to an<sup> </sup>open window, exposed to<sup> </sup>sun rays<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">remember the opposite<sup> </sup>excess of the painted<sup> </sup>content itself with regard<sup> </sup>to what we effectively<sup> </sup>see, as if we<sup> </sup>see only the fragment<sup> </sup>of the whole picture,<sup> </sup>the shot with a<sup> </sup>missing countershot), and, again,<sup> </sup>in Edvard Munch's <i>Madonna</i><sup> </sup>(the droplets of semen<sup> </sup>and the small fetuslike<sup> </sup>figure from <i>The Scream</i> squeezed<sup> </sup>in between the two<sup> </sup>frames). The frame is<sup> </sup>always already redoubled; the<sup> </sup>frame within "reality" is<sup> </sup>always linked to another<sup> </sup>frame enframing "reality" itself.<a href="#fn11" name="cfn11"><sup>11</sup></a><sup> </sup>Once introduced, the gap<sup> </sup>between reality and appearance<sup> </sup>is thus immediately complicated,<sup> </sup>reflected-into-itself; once we get<sup> </sup>a glimpse, through the<sup> </sup>Frame, of the Other<sup> </sup>Dimension, <i>reality itself turns into appearance</i>. In other<sup> </sup>words, things do not<sup> </sup>simply appear, they <i>appear to appear</i>.<sup> </sup>This is why the<sup> </sup>negation of a negation<sup> </sup>does not bring us<sup> </sup>to a simple flat<sup> </sup>affirmation. Once things (start<sup> </sup>to) appear, they not<sup> </sup>only appear as what<sup> </sup>they are not, creating<sup> </sup>an illusion; they can<sup> </sup>also appear to just<sup> </sup>appear, concealing the fact<sup> </sup>that they <i>are</i> what<sup> </sup>they appear.<sup> </sup></p>
<p>&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;This logic of<sup> </sup>the "minimal difference," of<sup> </sup>the constitutive noncoincidence of<sup> </sup>a thing with itself,<sup> </sup>provides the key to<sup> </sup>the central Hegelian category<sup> </sup>of concrete universality. Let<sup> </sup>us take a "mute"<sup> </sup>abstract universality that encompasses<sup> </sup>a set of elements<sup> </sup>all of which somehow<sup> </sup>subvert, do not fit,<sup> </sup>this universal frame. Is,<sup> </sup>in this case, the<sup> </sup>"true" concrete universal not<sup> </sup>this distance itself, the<sup> </sup>universalized exception? And, vice<sup> </sup>versa, is the element<sup> </sup>that directly fits the<sup> </sup>universal not the true<sup> </sup>exception? Universality is not<sup> </sup>the neutral container of<sup> </sup>particular formations, their common<sup> </sup>measure, the passive (back)ground<sup> </sup>on which the particulars<sup> </sup>fight their battles, but<sup> </sup><i>this battle itself,</i> the struggle leading<sup> </sup>from one to another<sup> </sup>particular formation. Recall Krzysztof<sup> </sup>Kie<img src="/ucp-entities/sacute.gif" alt="&amp;sacute;" align="bottom" border="0">lowski's passage from documentary<sup> </sup>to fiction cinema. We<sup> </sup>do not have simply<sup> </sup>two species of cinema,<sup> </sup>documentary and fiction; fiction<sup> </sup>emerges out of the<sup> </sup>inherent limitation of the<sup> </sup>documentary. Kie<img src="/ucp-entities/sacute.gif" alt="&amp;sacute;" align="bottom" border="0">lowski's starting point<sup> </sup>was the same as<sup> </sup>the one of all<sup> </sup>cineasts in the socialist<sup> </sup>countries: the conspicuous gap<sup> </sup>between the drab social<sup> </sup>reality and the optimistic,<sup> </sup>bright image that pervaded<sup> </sup>the heavily censored official<sup> </sup>media. The first reaction<sup> </sup>to the fact that,<sup> </sup>in Poland, social reality<sup> </sup>was "unrepresented," as Kie<img src="/ucp-entities/sacute.gif" alt="&amp;sacute;" align="bottom" border="0">lowski<sup> </sup>put it, was, of<sup> </sup>course, the move towards<sup> </sup>a more adequate representation<sup> </sup>of the real life<sup> </sup>in all its drabness<sup> </sup>and ambiguity<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">in short, an<sup> </sup>authentic documentary approach:
</p><blockquote><i>There<sup> </sup>was a necessity, a<sup> </sup>need<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">which was very exciting<sup> </sup>for us<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">to describe the<sup> </sup>world. The Communist world<sup> </sup>had described how it<sup> </sup>should be and not<sup> </sup>how it really was....<sup> </sup>If something hasn't been<sup> </sup>described, then it doesn't<sup> </sup>officially exist. So that<sup> </sup>if we start describing<sup> </sup>it, we bring it<sup> </sup>to life.<a href="#fn12" name="cfn12"><sup>12</sup></a></i><p></p>
</blockquote>
Suffice it<sup> </sup>to simply mention <i>Hospital</i>,<sup> </sup>Kie<img src="/ucp-entities/sacute.gif" alt="&amp;sacute;" align="bottom" border="0">lowski's documentary from 1976,<sup> </sup>in which the camera<sup> </sup>follows orthopedic surgeons on<sup> </sup>a thirty-two-hour shift. Instruments<sup> </sup>fall apart in their<sup> </sup>hands, the electrical current<sup> </sup>keeps breaking, there are<sup> </sup>shortages of the most<sup> </sup>basic materials, but the<sup> </sup>doctors persevere hour after<sup> </sup>hour, and with humor.<sup> </sup>Then, however, the obverse<sup> </sup>experience sets in, best<sup> </sup>captured by the slogan<sup> </sup>used recently to publicize<sup> </sup>a Hollywood movie: "It's<sup> </sup>so real, it must<sup> </sup>be fiction!" At the<sup> </sup>most radical level, one<sup> </sup>can render the Real<sup> </sup>of subjective experience only<sup> </sup>in the guise of<sup> </sup>a fiction. Towards the<sup> </sup>end of the documentary<sup> </sup><i>First Love</i> (1974), in which<sup> </sup>the camera follows a<sup> </sup>young unmarried couple during<sup> </sup>the girl's pregnancy, through<sup> </sup>their wedding, and ending<sup> </sup>with the delivery of<sup> </sup>the baby, the father<sup> </sup>is shown holding the<sup> </sup>newborn in his hands<sup> </sup>and crying. Kie<img src="/ucp-entities/sacute.gif" alt="&amp;sacute;" align="bottom" border="0">lowski reacted<sup> </sup>to the obscenity of<sup> </sup>such unwarranted probing into<sup> </sup>the other's intimacy with<sup> </sup>the "fright of real<sup> </sup>tears." His decision to<sup> </sup>pass from documentaries to<sup> </sup>fiction films was thus,<sup> </sup>at its most radical,<sup> </sup>an ethical one:
<blockquote><i>Not<sup> </sup>everything can be described.<sup> </sup>That's the documentary's great<sup> </sup>problem. It catches itself<sup> </sup>as if in its<sup> </sup>own trap.... If I'm<sup> </sup>making a film about<sup> </sup>love, I can't go<sup> </sup>into a bedroom if<sup> </sup>real people are making<sup> </sup>love there.... I noticed,<sup> </sup>when making documentaries, that<sup> </sup>the closer I wanted<sup> </sup>to get to an<sup> </sup>individual, the more objects<sup> </sup>which interested me shut<sup> </sup>themselves off.</i><p></p>
<i>That's probably why<sup> </sup>I changed to features.<sup> </sup>There's no problem there.<sup> </sup>I need a couple<sup> </sup>to make love in<sup> </sup>bed, that's fine. Of<sup> </sup>course, it might be<sup> </sup>difficult to find an<sup> </sup>actress who's willing to<sup> </sup>take off her bra,<sup> </sup>but then you just<sup> </sup>find one who is....<sup> </sup>I can even buy<sup> </sup>some glycerine, put some<sup> </sup>drops in her eyes<sup> </sup>and the actress will<sup> </sup>cry. I managed to<sup> </sup>photograph some real tears<sup> </sup>several times. It's something<sup> </sup>completely different. But now<sup> </sup>I've got glycerine. I'm<sup> </sup>frightened of those real<sup> </sup>tears. In fact, I<sup> </sup>don't know whether I've<sup> </sup>got the right to<sup> </sup>photograph them. At such<sup> </sup>times I feel like<sup> </sup>somebody who's found himself<sup> </sup>in a realm which<sup> </sup>is, in fact, out<sup> </sup>of bounds. That's the<sup> </sup>main reason why I<sup> </sup>escaped from documentaries.<a href="#fn13" name="cfn13"><sup>13</sup></a></i><p></p>
</blockquote>
The<sup> </sup>crucial intermediary in this<sup> </sup>passage from documentary to<sup> </sup>fiction is <i>Camera Buff</i> (1979),<sup> </sup>the portrait of a<sup> </sup>man who, because of<sup> </sup>his passion for the<sup> </sup>camera, loses his wife,<sup> </sup>child, and job<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">a fiction<sup> </sup>film about a documentary<sup> </sup>filmmaker. So there is<sup> </sup>a domain of fantasmatic<sup> </sup>intimacy that is marked<sup> </sup>by a No Trespassing!<sup> </sup>sign and should be<sup> </sup>approached only via fiction,<sup> </sup>if one is to<sup> </sup>avoid pornographic obscenity. This<sup> </sup>is the reason why<sup> </sup>the French Véronique in<sup> </sup><i>The Double Life of Véronique</i> rejects the puppeteer:<sup> </sup>he wants to penetrate<sup> </sup>her too much, which<sup> </sup>is why, towards the<sup> </sup>film's end, after he<sup> </sup>tells her the story<sup> </sup>of her double life,<sup> </sup>she is deeply hurt<sup> </sup>and escapes to her<sup> </sup>father.<a href="#fn14" name="cfn14"><sup>14</sup></a> "Concrete universality" is<sup> </sup>a name for this<sup> </sup>process through which fiction<sup> </sup>explodes <i>from within</i> documentary, that<sup> </sup>is, for the way<sup> </sup>the emergence of fiction<sup> </sup>cinema resolves the inherent<sup> </sup>deadlock of the documentary<sup> </sup>cinema. (Or, in philosophy,<sup> </sup>the point is not<sup> </sup>to conceive eternity as<sup> </sup>opposed to temporality, but<sup> </sup>eternity as it emerges<sup> </sup>from within our temporal<sup> </sup>experience<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">or, in an even<sup> </sup>more radical way, as<sup> </sup>Schelling did it, to<sup> </sup>conceive time itself as<sup> </sup>a subspecies of eternity,<sup> </sup>as the resolution of<sup> </sup>a deadlock of eternity.)<sup> </sup><p></p>
<p>&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;This<sup> </sup>brings us to the<sup> </sup>very heart of the<sup> </sup>concept of concrete universality.<sup> </sup>It is not merely<sup> </sup>the universal core that<sup> </sup>animates a series of<sup> </sup>its particular forms of<sup> </sup>appearance; it persists in<sup> </sup>the very irreducible tension,<sup> </sup>noncoincidence, between these different<sup> </sup>levels. Hegel is usually<sup> </sup>perceived as an "essentialist<sup> </sup>historicist," positing the spiritual<sup> </sup>"essence" of an epoch<sup> </sup>as a universal principle<sup> </sup>that expresses itself in<sup> </sup>a specific way in<sup> </sup>each domain of social<sup> </sup>life; say, the modern<sup> </sup>principle of subjectivity expresses<sup> </sup>itself in religion as<sup> </sup>Protestantism, in ethics as<sup> </sup>the subject's moral autonomy,<sup> </sup>in politics as democratic<sup> </sup>equality, and so on.<sup> </sup>What such a view<sup> </sup>misses is what one<sup> </sup>is tempted to call<sup> </sup>temporal parallax. In the<sup> </sup>complex dialectic of historical<sup> </sup>phenomena, we encounter events<sup> </sup>or processes that, although<sup> </sup>they are the actualization<sup> </sup>of the same underlying<sup> </sup>"principle" at different levels,<sup> </sup>cannot occur at the<sup> </sup>same historical moment. Recall<sup> </sup>the old topic of<sup> </sup>the relationship between Protestantism,<sup> </sup>Kantian philosophical revolution, and<sup> </sup>the French political revolution.<sup> </sup>Rebecca Comay recently refuted<sup> </sup>the myth that Hegel's<sup> </sup>critique of the French<sup> </sup>Revolution can be reduced<sup> </sup>to a variation of<sup> </sup>the "German" idea of<sup> </sup>how the Catholic French<sup> </sup>had to perform the<sup> </sup>violent "real" political revolution<sup> </sup>because they missed the<sup> </sup>historical moment of Reformation<sup> </sup>that already accomplished in<sup> </sup>the spiritual sphere the<sup> </sup>reconciliation between the spiritual<sup> </sup>Substance and the infinite<sup> </sup>subjectivity sought after in<sup> </sup>social reality by the<sup> </sup>revolutionaries. In this standard<sup> </sup>view, the German ethico-aesthetic<sup> </sup>attitude "sublates" revolutionary violence<sup> </sup>in the inner ethical<sup> </sup>order, thus enabling the<sup> </sup>replacement of the abstract<sup> </sup>"terrorist" revolutionary freedom by<sup> </sup>the concrete freedom of<sup> </sup>the state as an<sup> </sup>aesthetic organic whole. However,<sup> </sup>already the temporality of<sup> </sup>this relationship between the<sup> </sup>French political revolution and<sup> </sup>the German spiritual reformation<sup> </sup>is ambiguous. Three possible<sup> </sup>relations seem to overlap<sup> </sup>here. First, the idea<sup> </sup>of sublation points towards<sup> </sup>a succession; the French<sup> </sup>"immediate" unity of the<sup> </sup>Universal and the Subject<sup> </sup>is followed by its<sup> </sup>sublation, the German ethico-aesthetic<sup> </sup>mediation. Then, there is<sup> </sup>the idea of a<sup> </sup>simultaneous choice (or lack<sup> </sup>thereof), which made the<sup> </sup>two nations follow different<sup> </sup>paths: the Germans opted<sup> </sup>for Reformation, while the<sup> </sup>French remained within the<sup> </sup>Catholic universe and had<sup> </sup>thus to take the<sup> </sup>tortuous route of violent<sup> </sup>revolution. However, the empirical<sup> </sup>fact that Kant's philosophical<sup> </sup>revolution precedes the French<sup> </sup>Revolution is also not<sup> </sup>just an insignificant accident;<sup> </sup>in the spectacle of<sup> </sup>revolutionary Terror, Kantian ethics<sup> </sup>itself encounters the ultimate<sup> </sup>consequence of its own<sup> </sup>"abstract" character, so that<sup> </sup>Kant's philosophy should be<sup> </sup>read retroactively, through the<sup> </sup>prism of the French<sup> </sup>Revolution which enables us<sup> </sup>to perceive its limitations:<sup> </sup>
</p><blockquote><i>If [the Kantian moral<sup> </sup>view] presents itself as<sup> </sup>the narrative successor to<sup> </sup>the revolution, this is<sup> </sup>not because it logically<sup> </sup>fulfils or supersedes it:<sup> </sup>Kant's critical venture <i>phenomenologically</i><sup> </sup>succeeds the revolution that<sup> </sup>it <i>chronologically</i>, of course,<sup> </sup>anticipates only insofar as<sup> </sup>his text becomes legible<sup> </sup>only retroactively through the<sup> </sup>event that in institutionalizing<sup> </sup>the incessant short circuit<sup> </sup>of freedom and cruelty<sup> </sup>puts the project of<sup> </sup>modernity to its most<sup> </sup>extreme trial.... The revolution<sup> </sup>itself inflicts on Kant's<sup> </sup>own text a kind<sup> </sup>of retroactive trauma.<a href="#fn15" name="cfn15"><sup>15</sup></a></i><p></p>
</blockquote>
What<sup> </sup>this means is that<sup> </sup>the revolutionary Terror is<sup> </sup>a kind of obscene<sup> </sup>double of Kant's ethical<sup> </sup>thought: its destructive violence<sup> </sup>merely "externalizes" the terrorist<sup> </sup>potential of Kant's thought.<sup> </sup>This is why<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">and therein<sup> </sup>resides Hegel's central insight<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">it<sup> </sup>is hypocritical to reject<sup> </sup>the "excesses" of the<sup> </sup>French Revolution from the<sup> </sup>standpoint of the "German"<sup> </sup>moral view. All its<sup> </sup>terrifying features found their<sup> </sup>counterparts in, are contained<sup> </sup>and <i>repeated</i> within, the<sup> </sup>Kantian spiritual edifice (and<sup> </sup>the term <i>repetition</i> has<sup> </sup>to be given here<sup> </sup>the entire weight of<sup> </sup>Freud's <i>Wiederholungszwang</i>):
<blockquote><i>the purity<sup> </sup>of the moral will<sup> </sup>can be no antidote<sup> </sup>to the terrifying purity<sup> </sup>of revolutionary virtue. All<sup> </sup>the logical problems of<sup> </sup>absolute freedom are essentially<sup> </sup>carried over into Hegel's<sup> </sup>analysis of Kantian morality:<sup> </sup>the obsessionality, the paranoia,<sup> </sup>the suspicion, the evaporation<sup> </sup>of objectivity, within the<sup> </sup>violent hyperbole of a<sup> </sup>subjectivity bent on reproducing<sup> </sup>itself within a world<sup> </sup>it must disavow.<a href="#fn16" name="cfn16"><sup>16</sup></a></i><p></p>
</blockquote>
So,<sup> </sup>insofar as we are<sup> </sup>dealing here with a<sup> </sup>historical choice (between the<sup> </sup>"French" way of remaining<sup> </sup>within Catholicism, and thus<sup> </sup>being obliged to engage<sup> </sup>in the self-destructive revolutionary<sup> </sup>Terror, and the "German"<sup> </sup>way of Reformation), this<sup> </sup>choice involves exactly the<sup> </sup>same elementary dialectical paradox<sup> </sup>as the one, also<sup> </sup>from <i>The Phenomenology of Spirit</i>, between the<sup> </sup>two readings of "the<sup> </sup>Spirit is a bone,"<sup> </sup>which Hegel illustrates by<sup> </sup>the phallic metaphor<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">the phallus<sup> </sup>as the organ of<sup> </sup>insemination or phallus as<sup> </sup>the organ of urination.<sup> </sup>Hegel's point is <i>not</i><sup> </sup>that, in contrast to<sup> </sup>the vulgar empiricist mind<sup> </sup>that sees only urination,<sup> </sup>the proper speculative attitude<sup> </sup>has to choose insemination.<sup> </sup>The paradox is that<sup> </sup>the direct choice of<sup> </sup>insemination is the infallible<sup> </sup>way to miss it;<sup> </sup>it is not possible<sup> </sup>to choose directly the<sup> </sup>"true meaning." That is,<sup> </sup>one <i>has</i> to begin<sup> </sup>by making the "wrong"<sup> </sup>choice (of urination); the<sup> </sup>true speculative meaning emerges<sup> </sup>only through the repeated<sup> </sup>reading, as the aftereffect<sup> </sup>(or by-product) of the<sup> </sup>first, "wrong," reading. And<sup> </sup>the same goes for<sup> </sup>social life in which<sup> </sup>the direct choice of<sup> </sup>the concrete universality of<sup> </sup>a particular ethical life-world<sup> </sup>can only end in<sup> </sup>a regression to premodern<sup> </sup>organic society that denies<sup> </sup>the infinite right of<sup> </sup>subjectivity as the fundamental<sup> </sup>feature of modernity. Because<sup> </sup>the subject-citizen of a<sup> </sup>modern state can no<sup> </sup>longer accept his immersion<sup> </sup>in some particular social<sup> </sup>role that confers on<sup> </sup>him a determinate place<sup> </sup>within the organic social<sup> </sup>whole, the only way<sup> </sup>to the rational totality<sup> </sup>of the modern state<sup> </sup>leads through revolutionary Terror.<sup> </sup>One should ruthlessly tear<sup> </sup>up the constraints of<sup> </sup>premodern, organic, concrete universality,<sup> </sup>and fully assert the<sup> </sup>infinite right of subjectivity<sup> </sup>in its abstract negativity.<sup> </sup>In other words, the<sup> </sup>point of Hegel's analysis<sup> </sup>of the revolutionary Terror<sup> </sup>is not the rather<sup> </sup>obvious insight into how<sup> </sup>the revolutionary project involved<sup> </sup>the unilateral direct assertion<sup> </sup>of abstract Universal Reason<sup> </sup>and was as such<sup> </sup>doomed to perish in<sup> </sup>self-destructive fury, since it<sup> </sup>was unable to organize<sup> </sup>the transposition of its<sup> </sup>revolutionary energy into a<sup> </sup>concrete, stable, and differentiated<sup> </sup>social order. Hegel's point<sup> </sup>is rather the enigma<sup> </sup>of why, in spite<sup> </sup>of the fact that<sup> </sup>revolutionary Terror was a<sup> </sup>historical deadlock, we have<sup> </sup>to pass through it<sup> </sup>in order to arrive<sup> </sup>at the modern rational<sup> </sup>state. So, given again<sup> </sup>the choice between the<sup> </sup>Protestant "inner revolution" and<sup> </sup>the French violent political<sup> </sup>revolution, we see that<sup> </sup>Hegel is far from<sup> </sup>endorsing the German self-complacent<sup> </sup>superiority ("we made the<sup> </sup>right choice and can<sup> </sup>thus avoid revolutionary madness");<sup> </sup>precisely because Germans <i>made the right choice at a wrong time</i><sup> </sup>(<i>too early:</i> in the age<sup> </sup>of Reformation), they cannot<sup> </sup>gain access to the<sup> </sup>rational state that would<sup> </sup>be at the level<sup> </sup>of true political modernity.<sup> </sup>One should take another<sup> </sup>step here: it is<sup> </sup>not only that the<sup> </sup>universal Essence articulates itself<sup> </sup>in the discord between<sup> </sup>its particular forms of<sup> </sup>appearance; this discord is<sup> </sup>propelled by a gap<sup> </sup>that pertains to the<sup> </sup>very core of the<sup> </sup>universal Essence itself. In<sup> </sup>his book on modernity,<sup> </sup>Fredric Jameson refers to<sup> </sup>the Hegelian concrete universality<sup> </sup>in his concise critique<sup> </sup>of the recently fashionable<sup> </sup>theories of "alternate modernities":<sup> </sup>
<blockquote><i>How then can the<sup> </sup>ideologues of "modernity" in<sup> </sup>its current sense manage<sup> </sup>to distinguish their product<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">the<sup> </sup>information revolution, and globalized,<sup> </sup>free-market modernity<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">from the detestable<sup> </sup>older kind, without getting<sup> </sup>themselves involved in asking<sup> </sup>the kinds of serious<sup> </sup>political and economic, systemic<sup> </sup>questions that the concept<sup> </sup>of a postmodernity makes<sup> </sup>unavoidable? The answer is<sup> </sup>simple: you talk about<sup> </sup>"alternate" or "alternative" modernities.<sup> </sup>Everyone knows the formula<sup> </sup>by now: this means<sup> </sup>that there can be<sup> </sup>a modernity for everybody<sup> </sup>which is different from<sup> </sup>the standard or hegemonic<sup> </sup>Anglo-Saxon model. Whatever you<sup> </sup>dislike about the latter,<sup> </sup>including the subaltern position<sup> </sup>it leaves you in,<sup> </sup>can be effaced by<sup> </sup>the reassuring and "cultural"<sup> </sup>notion that you can<sup> </sup>fashion your own modernity<sup> </sup>differently, so that there<sup> </sup>can be a Latin-American<sup> </sup>kind, or an Indian<sup> </sup>kind or an African<sup> </sup>kind, and so on....<sup> </sup>But this is to<sup> </sup>overlook the other fundamental<sup> </sup>meaning of modernity which<sup> </sup>is that of a<sup> </sup>worldwide capitalism itself.<a href="#fn17" name="cfn17"><sup>17</sup></a></i><p></p>
</blockquote>
The<sup> </sup>significance of this critique<sup> </sup>reaches far beyond the<sup> </sup>case of modernity; it<sup> </sup>concerns the fundamental limitation<sup> </sup>of the nominalist historicizing.<sup> </sup>The recourse to multitude<sup> </sup>(there is not one<sup> </sup>modernity with a fixed<sup> </sup>essence, there are multiple<sup> </sup>modernities, each of them<sup> </sup>irreducible to others) is<sup> </sup>false not because it<sup> </sup>does not recognize a<sup> </sup>unique fixed "essence" of<sup> </sup>modernity but because multiplication<sup> </sup>functions as the disavowal<sup> </sup>of the antagonism that<sup> </sup>inheres to the notion<sup> </sup>of modernity as such;<sup> </sup>the falsity of multiplication<sup> </sup>resides in the fact<sup> </sup>that it frees the<sup> </sup>universal notion of modernity<sup> </sup>from its antagonism, from<sup> </sup>the way it is<sup> </sup>embedded in the capitalist<sup> </sup>system, by relegating this<sup> </sup>aspect to just one<sup> </sup>of its historical subspecies.<sup> </sup>(One should not forget<sup> </sup>that the first half<sup> </sup>of the twentieth century<sup> </sup>already was marked by<sup> </sup>two big projects that<sup> </sup>perfectly fit this notion<sup> </sup>of alternate modernity: Fascism<sup> </sup>and Communism. Was not<sup> </sup>the basic idea of<sup> </sup>Fascism that of a<sup> </sup>modernity which provides an<sup> </sup>alternative to standard, Anglo-Saxon,<sup> </sup>liberal-capitalist modernity, of saving<sup> </sup>the core of capitalist<sup> </sup>modernity by casting away<sup> </sup>its "contingent," Jewish-individualist-profiteering distortion?<sup> </sup>And was not the<sup> </sup>rapid industrialization of the<sup> </sup>USSR in the late<sup> </sup>1920s and 1930s also<sup> </sup>an attempt at modernization<sup> </sup>different from the Western-capitalist<sup> </sup>one?) And, insofar as<sup> </sup>this inherent antagonism could<sup> </sup>be designated as a<sup> </sup>"castrative" dimension and, furthermore,<sup> </sup>insofar as, according to<sup> </sup>Freud, the disavowal of<sup> </sup>castration is represented as<sup> </sup>the multiplication of the<sup> </sup>phallus-representatives (a multitude of<sup> </sup>phalluses signals castration, the<sup> </sup>lack of the one),<sup> </sup>it is easy to<sup> </sup>conceive such a multiplication<sup> </sup>of modernities as a<sup> </sup>form of fetishist disavowal.<sup> </sup><p></p>
<p>&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;Jameson's<sup> </sup>critique of the notion<sup> </sup>of alternate modernities thus<sup> </sup>provides a model of<sup> </sup>the properly <i>dialectical</i> relationship<sup> </sup>between the Universal and<sup> </sup>the Particular; the difference<sup> </sup>is not on the<sup> </sup>side of particular content<sup> </sup>(as the traditional <i>differentia specifica</i>)<sup> </sup>but on the side<sup> </sup>of the Universal. The<sup> </sup>Universal is not the<sup> </sup>encompassing container of the<sup> </sup>particular content, the peaceful<sup> </sup>medium background of the<sup> </sup>conflict of particularities; the<sup> </sup>Universal as such is<sup> </sup>the site of an<sup> </sup>unbearable antagonism, self-contradiction, and<sup> </sup>(the multitude of) its<sup> </sup>particular species are ultimately<sup> </sup>nothing but so many<sup> </sup>attempts to obfuscate, reconcile,<sup> </sup>master this antagonism. In<sup> </sup>other words, the Universal<sup> </sup>names the site of<sup> </sup>a problem-deadlock, of a<sup> </sup>burning question, and the<sup> </sup>particulars are the attempted<sup> </sup>but failed answers to<sup> </sup>this problem. Say that<sup> </sup>the concept of state<sup> </sup>names a certain problem:<sup> </sup>how to contain the<sup> </sup>class antagonism of a<sup> </sup>society? All particular forms<sup> </sup>of state are so<sup> </sup>many (failed) attempts to<sup> </sup>propose a solution for<sup> </sup>this problem.<sup> </sup></p>
<p>&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;This is how<sup> </sup>one should answer the<sup> </sup>standard critique of Christian<sup> </sup>universalism: what this all-inclusive<sup> </sup>attitude (recall St. Paul's<sup> </sup>famous statement, "Where there<sup> </sup>is neither Greek nor<sup> </sup>Jew" [Col. 3:11]) involves<sup> </sup>is a thorough exclusion<sup> </sup>of those who do<sup> </sup>not accept Christianity. In<sup> </sup>other "particularistic" religions (and<sup> </sup>even in Islam, in<sup> </sup>spite of its global<sup> </sup>expansionism), there is a<sup> </sup>place for others, they<sup> </sup>are tolerated, even if<sup> </sup>they are condescendingly looked<sup> </sup>upon. The Christian motto,<sup> </sup>All Men Are Brothers,<sup> </sup>however, means also that<sup> </sup>those who are not<sup> </sup>my brothers <i>are not (even) men.</i> Christians<sup> </sup>usually praise themselves for<sup> </sup>overcoming the Jewish exclusivist<sup> </sup>notion of the Chosen<sup> </sup>People and encompassing the<sup> </sup>entirety of humanity<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">the catch<sup> </sup>here is that, in<sup> </sup>their very insistence that<sup> </sup>they are the Chosen<sup> </sup>People with the privileged<sup> </sup>direct link to God,<sup> </sup>Jews accept the humanity<sup> </sup>of the other people<sup> </sup>who celebrate their false<sup> </sup>gods, while Christian universalism<sup> </sup>tendentiously excludes nonbelievers from<sup> </sup>the very universality of<sup> </sup>humankind.<sup> </sup></p>
<p>&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;Thus Christian universality is<sup> </sup>not the all-encompassing global<sup> </sup>medium where there is<sup> </sup>a place for all<sup> </sup>and everyone. It is<sup> </sup>rather the <i>struggling</i> universality,<sup> </sup>the site of a<sup> </sup>constant battle. Which battle,<sup> </sup>which division? To follow<sup> </sup>Paul: <i>not</i> the division<sup> </sup>between Law and sin,<sup> </sup>but between, on the<sup> </sup>one side, the <i>totality</i><sup> </sup>of Law and sin<sup> </sup>as its supplement and,<sup> </sup>on the other side,<sup> </sup>the way of Love.<sup> </sup>Christian universality emerges at<sup> </sup>the symptomal point of<sup> </sup>those who are "part<sup> </sup>of no-part" of the<sup> </sup>global order. This is<sup> </sup>where the reproach of<sup> </sup>exclusion gets it wrong:<sup> </sup>Christian universality, far from<sup> </sup>excluding some subjects, <i>is formulated from the position of those excluded</i>,<sup> </sup>of those for whom<sup> </sup>there is no specific<sup> </sup>place within the existing<sup> </sup>order, although they belong<sup> </sup>to it; universality is<sup> </sup>strictly codependent with this<sup> </sup>lack of specific place/determination.<sup> </sup></p>
<p>&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;Or,<sup> </sup>to put it in<sup> </sup>a different way, the<sup> </sup>reproach to Paul's universalism<sup> </sup>misses the true site<sup> </sup>of universality. The universal<sup> </sup>dimension he opened up<sup> </sup>is not the "neither<sup> </sup>Greeks nor Jews but<sup> </sup>all Christians," which implicitly<sup> </sup>excludes non-Christians; <i>it is rather the difference Christians/non-Christians itself which, as a difference, is universal</i>; that<sup> </sup>is, it cuts across<sup> </sup>the entire social body,<sup> </sup>splitting, dividing from within<sup> </sup>every kind of ethnic<sup> </sup>identity: Greeks are cut<sup> </sup>into Christians and non-Christians,<sup> </sup>as well as Jews.<sup> </sup>The standard reproach thus<sup> </sup>in a way knocks<sup> </sup>on an open door.<sup> </sup>The whole point of<sup> </sup>the Paulinian notion of<sup> </sup>struggling universality <i>is</i> that<sup> </sup>true universality and partiality<sup> </sup>do not exclude each<sup> </sup>other and also that<sup> </sup><i>universal Truth is only accessible from a partial, engaged, subjective position</i>.<sup> </sup></p>
<p>&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;For strategic reasons, my<sup> </sup>master signifier for the<sup> </sup>"minimal difference" is not<sup> </sup><i>différance</i>, but <i>parallax</i>. The<sup> </sup>common definition of parallax<sup> </sup>is the apparent displacement<sup> </sup>of an object (the<sup> </sup>shift of its position<sup> </sup>against a background) caused<sup> </sup>by a change in<sup> </sup>observational position that provides<sup> </sup>a new line of<sup> </sup>sight. The philosophical twist<sup> </sup>to be added, of<sup> </sup>course, is that the<sup> </sup>observed difference is not<sup> </sup>simply subjective, because the<sup> </sup>same object is seen<sup> </sup>from two different stations<sup> </sup>or points of view.<sup> </sup>It is rather that,<sup> </sup>as Hegel would have<sup> </sup>put it, subject and<sup> </sup>object are inherently "mediated,"<sup> </sup>so that an "epistemological"<sup> </sup>shift in the subject's<sup> </sup>point of view always<sup> </sup>reflects an "ontological" shift<sup> </sup>in the object itself.<sup> </sup>Or, to put it<sup> </sup>in Lacanese, the subject's<sup> </sup>gaze is always already<sup> </sup>inscribed into the perceived<sup> </sup>object itself, in the<sup> </sup>guise of its "blind<sup> </sup>spot," that which is<sup> </sup>in the object more<sup> </sup>than object itself, the<sup> </sup>point from which the<sup> </sup>object itself returns the<sup> </sup>gaze. Sure, the picture<sup> </sup>is in my eye,<sup> </sup>but me, I am<sup> </sup>also in the picture.<a href="#fn18" name="cfn18"><sup>18</sup></a><sup> </sup>The first part of<sup> </sup>this Lacanian statement designates<sup> </sup>subjectivization, the dependence of<sup> </sup>reality on its subjective<sup> </sup>constitution, while its second<sup> </sup>part provides a materialist<sup> </sup>supplement, reinscribing the subject<sup> </sup>into its own image<sup> </sup>in the guise of<sup> </sup>a stain (the objectivized<sup> </sup>splinter in its eye).<sup> </sup>Materialism is not the<sup> </sup>direct assertion of my<sup> </sup>inclusion into the objective<sup> </sup>reality (such an assertion<sup> </sup>presupposes that my position<sup> </sup>of enunciation is that<sup> </sup>of an external observer<sup> </sup>who can grasp the<sup> </sup>whole of reality); it<sup> </sup>rather resides in the<sup> </sup>reflexive twist by means<sup> </sup>of which I myself<sup> </sup>am included into the<sup> </sup>picture constituted by me.<sup> </sup>It is this reflexive<sup> </sup>short circuit, this necessary<sup> </sup><i>redoubling</i> of myself as<sup> </sup>standing outside <i>and</i> inside<sup> </sup>my picture, that bears<sup> </sup>witness to my material<sup> </sup>existence. Materialism means that<sup> </sup>the reality I see<sup> </sup>is never whole<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">not because<sup> </sup>a large part of<sup> </sup>it eludes me but<sup> </sup>because it contains a<sup> </sup>stain, a blind spot,<sup> </sup>which signals my inclusion<sup> </sup>in it.<sup> </sup></p>
<p>&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;Nowhere is this<sup> </sup>structure clearer than in<sup> </sup>the case of Lacan's<sup> </sup><i>objet petit a</i>, the object-cause of<sup> </sup>desire. The same object<sup> </sup>can all of a<sup> </sup>sudden be "transubstantiated" into<sup> </sup>the object of my<sup> </sup>desire. What is to<sup> </sup>you just an ordinary<sup> </sup>object is for me<sup> </sup>the focus of my<sup> </sup>libidinal investment, and this<sup> </sup>shift is caused by<sup> </sup>some unfathomable <i>x,</i> a<sup> </sup><i>je ne sais quoi</i> in the object<sup> </sup>that cannot ever be<sup> </sup>pinned down to any<sup> </sup>of its particular properties.<sup> </sup><i>Objet a</i> is therefore close<sup> </sup>to the Kantian transcendental<sup> </sup>object because it stands<sup> </sup>for the unknown <i>x,</i><sup> </sup>the noumenal core of<sup> </sup>the object beyond appearances,<sup> </sup>for what is "in<sup> </sup>you more than yourself."<sup> </sup><i>L'objet petit a</i> can thus be<sup> </sup>defined as a pure<sup> </sup>parallax object: not only<sup> </sup>do its contours change<sup> </sup>with the shift of<sup> </sup>the subject; <i>it only exists<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">its presence can only be discerned<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">when the landscape is viewed from a certain perspective</i>. More<sup> </sup>precisely, the object <i>a</i><sup> </sup>is the very <i>cause</i><sup> </sup>of the parallax gap,<sup> </sup>that unfathomable <i>x</i> which<sup> </sup>forever eludes the symbolic<sup> </sup>grasp and thus causes<sup> </sup>the multiplicity of symbolic<sup> </sup>perspectives. The paradox here<sup> </sup>is a very precise<sup> </sup>one: it is at<sup> </sup>the very point at<sup> </sup>which a pure difference<sup> </sup>emerges<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">a difference that is<sup> </sup>no longer a difference<sup> </sup>between two positively existing<sup> </sup>objects, but a minimal<sup> </sup>difference that divides one<sup> </sup>and the same object<sup> </sup>from itself<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">that this difference<sup> </sup>as such immediately coincides<sup> </sup>with an unfathomable object.<sup> </sup>In contrast to a<sup> </sup>mere difference between objects,<sup> </sup><i>the pure difference is itself an object</i>. The parallax gap,<sup> </sup>the minimal difference, is<sup> </sup>a pure difference that<sup> </sup>cannot be grounded in<sup> </sup>positive substantial properties. In<sup> </sup>Henry James's "The Real<sup> </sup>Thing," the painter-narrator agrees<sup> </sup>to hire the impoverished<sup> </sup>"true" aristocrats Major and<sup> </sup>Mrs. Monarch as models<sup> </sup>for his illustrations of<sup> </sup>a deluxe book. However,<sup> </sup>although they are the<sup> </sup>"real thing," their drawings<sup> </sup>appear fake, so the<sup> </sup>painter must rely more<sup> </sup>and more on a<sup> </sup>vulgar couple, Miss Churm<sup> </sup>and the lithe Italian<sup> </sup>Oronte, whose imitation of<sup> </sup>high-class poses works much<sup> </sup>better. Is this not<sup> </sup>the unfathomable "minimal difference"<sup> </sup>at its purest?<sup> </sup></p>
<p>&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;Jacques-Alain Miller<sup> </sup>recently proposed a Benjaminian<sup> </sup>distinction between "constituted anxiety"<sup> </sup>and "constituent anxiety," which<sup> </sup>is crucial with regard<sup> </sup>to the shift from<sup> </sup>desire to drive. While<sup> </sup>the first one designated<sup> </sup>the standard notion of<sup> </sup>the terrifying and fascinating<sup> </sup>abyss of anxiety that<sup> </sup>haunts us, its infernal<sup> </sup>circle that threatens to<sup> </sup>draw us in, the<sup> </sup>second one stands for<sup> </sup>the "pure" confrontation with<sup> </sup><i>objet petit a</i> as constituted in<sup> </sup>its very loss.<a href="#fn19" name="cfn19"><sup>19</sup></a> Miller<sup> </sup>is right to emphasize<sup> </sup>here two features: the<sup> </sup>difference that separates constituted<sup> </sup>from constituent anxiety concerns<sup> </sup>the status of the<sup> </sup>object with regard to<sup> </sup>fantasy. In a case<sup> </sup>of constituted anxiety, the<sup> </sup>object dwells within the<sup> </sup>confines of a fantasy,<sup> </sup>while we only get<sup> </sup>the constituent anxiety when<sup> </sup>the subject "traverses the<sup> </sup>fantasy" and confronts the<sup> </sup>void, the gap, filled<sup> </sup>up by the fantasmatic<sup> </sup>object. As Mallarmé put<sup> </sup>it in the famous<sup> </sup>parenthetical lines of his<sup> </sup>so-called sonnet <i>en <img src="/ucp-entities/ndash.gif" alt="–" align="bottom" border="0">yx, objet a</i> is<sup> </sup>"ce seul objet dont<sup> </sup>le Neant s'honore" ("this<sup> </sup>sole object with which<sup> </sup>Nothing is honored").<sup> </sup></p>
<p>&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;Clear and<sup> </sup>convincing as it is,<sup> </sup>Miller's formula misses the<sup> </sup>true paradox or, rather,<sup> </sup>ambiguity of <i>objet a</i>. When<sup> </sup>he defines <i>objet a</i> as<sup> </sup>the object that overlaps<sup> </sup>with its loss, which<sup> </sup>emerges at the very<sup> </sup>moment of its loss<sup> </sup>(so that all its<sup> </sup>fantasmatic incarnations, from breasts<sup> </sup>to voice and gaze,<sup> </sup>are metonymic figurations of<sup> </sup>the void, of nothing),<sup> </sup>he remains within the<sup> </sup>horizon of <i>desire</i>. The<sup> </sup>true object-cause of desire<sup> </sup>is the void filled<sup> </sup>in by its fantasmatic<sup> </sup>incarnations. While, as Lacan<sup> </sup>emphasizes, <i>objet a</i> is also<sup> </sup>the object of drive,<sup> </sup>the relationship is here<sup> </sup>thoroughly different: although, in<sup> </sup>both cases, the link<sup> </sup>between object and loss<sup> </sup>is crucial, in the<sup> </sup>case of <i>objet a</i> as<sup> </sup>the object-cause of <i>desire</i>,<sup> </sup>we have an object<sup> </sup>that is originally lost,<sup> </sup>that coincides with its<sup> </sup>own loss, that emerges<sup> </sup>as lost; in the<sup> </sup>case of <i>objet a</i> as<sup> </sup>the object of drive,<sup> </sup>the "object" <i>is directly the loss itself.</i> In<sup> </sup>the shift from desire<sup> </sup>to drive, we pass<sup> </sup>from the <i>lost object</i> to<sup> </sup><i>loss itself as an object</i>. That is to<sup> </sup>say, the weird movement<sup> </sup>called drive is not<sup> </sup>driven by the "impossible"<sup> </sup>quest for the lost<sup> </sup>object; it is <i>a push to directly enact the "loss"<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">the gap, cut, distance<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">itself</i>.<sup> </sup>There is thus a<sup> </sup><i>double</i> distinction to be<sup> </sup>drawn here: not only<sup> </sup>between <i>objet a</i> in its<sup> </sup>fantasmatic and postfantasmatic status<sup> </sup>but also, within this<sup> </sup>postfantasmatic domain itself, between<sup> </sup>the lost object-cause of<sup> </sup>desire and the object-loss<sup> </sup>of drive.<sup> </sup></p>
<p>&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;This is why<sup> </sup>one should not confuse<sup> </sup>the death drive with<sup> </sup>the so-called nirvana principle,<sup> </sup>the thrust towards destruction<sup> </sup>or self-obliteration; the Freudian<sup> </sup>death drive has nothing<sup> </sup>whatsoever to do with<sup> </sup>the craving for self-annihilation,<sup> </sup>for the return to<sup> </sup>the inorganic absence of<sup> </sup>any life tension. It<sup> </sup>is, on the contrary,<sup> </sup>the very opposite of<sup> </sup>dying<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">a name for the<sup> </sup>"undead" eternal life itself,<sup> </sup>for the horrible fate<sup> </sup>of being caught in<sup> </sup>the endless repetitive cycle<sup> </sup>of wandering around in<sup> </sup>guilt and pain. The<sup> </sup>paradox of the Freudian<sup> </sup>death drive is therefore<sup> </sup>that it is Freud's<sup> </sup>name for its very<sup> </sup>opposite, for the way<sup> </sup>immortality appears within psychoanalysis,<sup> </sup>for an uncanny <i>excess</i><sup> </sup>of life, for an<sup> </sup>"undead" urge that persists<sup> </sup>beyond the (biological) cycle<sup> </sup>of life and death,<sup> </sup>of generation and corruption.<sup> </sup>The ultimate lesson of<sup> </sup>psychoanalysis is that human<sup> </sup>life is never just<sup> </sup>life. Humans are not<sup> </sup>simply alive; they are<sup> </sup>possessed by the strange<sup> </sup>drive to enjoy life<sup> </sup>in excess, passionately attached<sup> </sup>to a surplus that<sup> </sup>sticks out and derails<sup> </sup>the ordinary run of<sup> </sup>things.<sup> </sup></p>
<p>&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;What this means is<sup> </sup>that it is wrong<sup> </sup>to claim that the<sup> </sup>"pure" death drive would<sup> </sup>have been the impossible<sup> </sup>"total" will to (self)-destruction,<sup> </sup>the ecstatic self-annihilation in<sup> </sup>which the subject would<sup> </sup>have rejoined the fullness<sup> </sup>of the maternal Thing<sup> </sup>but that this will<sup> </sup>is not realizable, that<sup> </sup>it gets blocked, stuck<sup> </sup>to a "partial object."<sup> </sup>Such a notion retranslates<sup> </sup>death drive into the<sup> </sup>terms of desire and<sup> </sup>its lost object. It<sup> </sup>is in desire that<sup> </sup>the positive object is<sup> </sup>a metonymic stand-in for<sup> </sup>the void of the<sup> </sup>impossible Thing; it is<sup> </sup>in desire that the<sup> </sup>aspiration to fullness is<sup> </sup>transferred to partial objects.<sup> </sup>This is what Lacan<sup> </sup>called the metonymy of<sup> </sup>desire. One has to<sup> </sup>be very precise here<sup> </sup>if we are not<sup> </sup>to miss Lacan's point<sup> </sup>(and thereby confuse desire<sup> </sup>and drive): drive is<sup> </sup>not an infinite longing<sup> </sup>for the Thing that<sup> </sup>gets fixated onto a<sup> </sup>partial object; a drive<sup> </sup><i>is</i> this fixation itself<sup> </sup>in which resides the<sup> </sup>"death" dimension of every<sup> </sup>drive. A drive is<sup> </sup>not a universal thrust<sup> </sup>(towards the incestuous Thing)<sup> </sup>braked and broken up.<sup> </sup>It <i>is</i> this brake<sup> </sup>itself, a brake on<sup> </sup>instinct, its "stuckness," as<sup> </sup>Eric Santner would have<sup> </sup>put it.<a href="#fn20" name="cfn20"><sup>20</sup></a> The elementary<sup> </sup>matrix of drive is<sup> </sup><i>not</i> that of transcending<sup> </sup>all particular objects towards<sup> </sup>the void of the<sup> </sup>Thing (which is then<sup> </sup>accessible only in its<sup> </sup>metonymic stand-in) but that<sup> </sup>of our libido getting<sup> </sup>"stuck" onto a particular<sup> </sup>object, condemned to circulate<sup> </sup>around it forever.<sup> </sup></p>
<p>&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;The basic<sup> </sup>paradox here is that<sup> </sup>the specifically human dimension<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">drive<sup> </sup>as opposed to instinct<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">emerges<sup> </sup>precisely when what was<sup> </sup>originally a mere by-product<sup> </sup>is elevated into an<sup> </sup>autonomous aim. Man is<sup> </sup>not more "reflexive"; on<sup> </sup>the contrary, man perceives<sup> </sup>as a direct goal<sup> </sup>what, for an animal,<sup> </sup>has no intrinsic value.<sup> </sup>In short, the zero-degree<sup> </sup>of being human is<sup> </sup>not a further "mediation"<sup> </sup>of animal activity, its<sup> </sup>reinscription as a subordinated<sup> </sup>moment of a higher<sup> </sup>totality (say, we eat<sup> </sup>and procreate in order<sup> </sup>to develop higher spiritual<sup> </sup>potentials), but the radical<sup> </sup>narrowing of focus, the<sup> </sup>elevation of a minor<sup> </sup>activity into an end<sup> </sup>in itself. We become<sup> </sup>humans when we get<sup> </sup>caught in a closed,<sup> </sup>self-propelling loop of repeating<sup> </sup>the same gesture and<sup> </sup>finding satisfaction in it.<sup> </sup>We all recall one<sup> </sup>of the archetypal scenes<sup> </sup>from cartoons: while dancing,<sup> </sup>the cat jumps up<sup> </sup>into the air and<sup> </sup>turns around its own<sup> </sup>axis; however, instead of<sup> </sup>falling back down towards<sup> </sup>the earth's surface in<sup> </sup>accordance with the normal<sup> </sup>laws of gravity, it<sup> </sup>remains for some time<sup> </sup>suspended in the air,<sup> </sup>turning around in the<sup> </sup>levitated position as if<sup> </sup>caught in a loop<sup> </sup>of time, repeating the<sup> </sup>same circular movement on<sup> </sup>and on. (One also<sup> </sup>finds the same image<sup> </sup>in some musical comedies<sup> </sup>that make use of<sup> </sup>the elements of slapstick;<sup> </sup>when a dancer turns<sup> </sup>around in the air,<sup> </sup>he or she remains<sup> </sup>up there a little<sup> </sup>bit too long, as<sup> </sup>if, for a short<sup> </sup>period of time, he<sup> </sup>or she had succeeded<sup> </sup>in suspending the law<sup> </sup>of gravity. And, in<sup> </sup>essence, is such an<sup> </sup>effect not the ultimate<sup> </sup>goal of the art<sup> </sup>of dancing?) In such<sup> </sup>moments, the "normal" run<sup> </sup>of things, the "normal"<sup> </sup>process of being caught<sup> </sup>in the imbecilic inertia<sup> </sup>of material reality, is<sup> </sup>for a brief moment<sup> </sup>suspended; we enter the<sup> </sup>magical domain of suspended<sup> </sup>animation, of a kind<sup> </sup>of ethereal rotation that,<sup> </sup>as it were, sustains<sup> </sup>itself, hanging in the<sup> </sup>air like Baron Munchhausen<sup> </sup>who raised himself from<sup> </sup>the swamp by grabbing<sup> </sup>his own hair and<sup> </sup>pulling himself up. This<sup> </sup>rotary movement, in which<sup> </sup>the liberal progress of<sup> </sup>time is suspended in<sup> </sup>a repetitive loop, is<sup> </sup><i>drive</i> at its most<sup> </sup>elementary. This, again, is<sup> </sup>"humanization" at its zero-level:<sup> </sup>this self-propelling loop that<sup> </sup>suspends or disrupts linear<sup> </sup>temporal enchainment.<sup> </sup></p>
<p>&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;Consequently, the concept<sup> </sup>of drive makes the<sup> </sup>alternatives "either burned by<sup> </sup>the Thing or maintaining<sup> </sup>a distance" false. In<sup> </sup>a drive, the thing<sup> </sup>itself is a circulation<sup> </sup>around the void (or,<sup> </sup>rather, hole, not void).<sup> </sup>To put it even<sup> </sup>more pointedly, the object<sup> </sup>of drive is not<sup> </sup>related to the Thing<sup> </sup>as a filler of<sup> </sup>its void; drive is<sup> </sup>literally a countermovement to<sup> </sup>desire. It does not<sup> </sup>strive towards impossible fullness<sup> </sup>and, being forced to<sup> </sup>renounce it, get stuck<sup> </sup>onto a partial object<sup> </sup>as its remainder. Drive<sup> </sup>is quite literally <i>the very "drive" to break the all of the continuity in which we are embedded</i>,<sup> </sup>to introduce a radical<sup> </sup>imbalance into it, and<sup> </sup>the difference between drive<sup> </sup>and desire is precisely<sup> </sup>that, in desire, this<sup> </sup>cut, this fixation onto<sup> </sup>a partial object, is<sup> </sup>as it were "transcendentalized,"<sup> </sup>transposed into a stand-in<sup> </sup>for the void of<sup> </sup>the Thing.<sup> </sup></p>
<p>&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;This is also<sup> </sup>how one should read<sup> </sup>Lacan's thesis on the<sup> </sup>satisfaction of drives. A<sup> </sup>drive does not bring<sup> </sup>satisfaction because its object<sup> </sup>is a stand-in for<sup> </sup>the Thing but because<sup> </sup>a drive as it<sup> </sup>were turns failure into<sup> </sup>triumph. In it, the<sup> </sup>very failure to reach<sup> </sup>its goal, the repetition<sup> </sup>of this failure, the<sup> </sup>endless circulation around the<sup> </sup>object, generates a satisfaction<sup> </sup>of its own. As<sup> </sup>Lacan put it, the<sup> </sup>true aim of a<sup> </sup>drive is not to<sup> </sup>reach its goal but<sup> </sup>to circulate endlessly around<sup> </sup>it. In the well-known<sup> </sup>vulgar joke about a<sup> </sup>fool having intercourse for<sup> </sup>the first time, the<sup> </sup>girl has to tell<sup> </sup>him exactly what to<sup> </sup>do: "See this hole<sup> </sup>between my legs? Put<sup> </sup>it in here. Now<sup> </sup>push it deep. Now<sup> </sup>pull it out. Push<sup> </sup>it in, pull it<sup> </sup>out, push it in,<sup> </sup>pull it out..." "Now<sup> </sup>wait a minute," the<sup> </sup>fool interrupts her, "make<sup> </sup>up your mind! In<sup> </sup>or out?" What the<sup> </sup>fool misses is precisely<sup> </sup>the structure of a<sup> </sup>drive that gets its<sup> </sup>satisfaction from the indecision<sup> </sup>itself, from repeated oscillation.<sup> </sup></p><hr align="center" noshade="noshade" width="60">
<p>&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;And,<sup> </sup>because we end with<sup> </sup>a dirty joke, we<sup> </sup>should perhaps conclude in<sup> </sup>a lighter mode. In<sup> </sup>the documentary <i>Derrida</i>, in<sup> </sup>answer to the question<sup> </sup>what he would ask<sup> </sup>some great classic philosopher<sup> </sup>if he were to<sup> </sup>meet him, Derrida immediately<sup> </sup>snaps back: "About his<sup> </sup>sex life." Here, perhaps,<sup> </sup>one should supplement Derrida.<sup> </sup>In directly asking this<sup> </sup>question, one would probably<sup> </sup>get a common answer;<sup> </sup>the thing to look<sup> </sup>for would be rather<sup> </sup>the <i>theory</i> about sexuality<sup> </sup>at the level of<sup> </sup>their respective philosophies. Perhaps<sup> </sup>the ultimate philosophical fantasy<sup> </sup>would be here the<sup> </sup>discovery of a manuscript<sup> </sup>in which Hegel, the<sup> </sup>systematician <i>par excellence</i>, develops a<sup> </sup>system of sexuality, of<sup> </sup>sexual practices contradicting, inverting,<sup> </sup>sublating each other, deducing<sup> </sup>all (straight and "perverse")<sup> </sup>forms from the basic<sup> </sup>deadlock.<a href="#fn21" name="cfn21"><sup>21</sup></a> As in Hegel's<sup> </sup><i>Encyclopedia</i>, we would first<sup> </sup>get the deduction of<sup> </sup>the main "subjective attitudes<sup> </sup>towards sex" (animal coupling,<sup> </sup>pure excessive lust, expression<sup> </sup>of human love, metaphysical<sup> </sup>passion), followed by the<sup> </sup>proper "system of sexuality,"<sup> </sup>organized, as one would<sup> </sup>expect it from Hegel,<sup> </sup>into a sequence of<sup> </sup>triads. The starting point<sup> </sup>is here copulation <i>a tergo</i>,<sup> </sup>sexual act in its<sup> </sup>animal, presubjective immediacy; we<sup> </sup>then pass to its<sup> </sup>immediate (abstract) negation<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">masturbation<img src="/ucp-entities/mdash.gif" alt="—" align="bottom" border="0">in which<sup> </sup>lone self-excitation is supplemented<sup> </sup>by fantasizing. (Jean Laplanche<sup> </sup>has shown how masturbation-with-fantasy<sup> </sup>is the elementary, zero-level<sup> </sup>form of the properly<sup> </sup>human drive as opposed<sup> </sup>to the animal instinct.)<sup> </sup>What follows is the<sup> </sup>synthesis of the two:<sup> </sup>sexual act proper in<sup> </sup>a missionary position, in<sup> </sup>which the face-to-face contact<sup> </sup>guarantees that the full<sup> </sup>bodily contact (penetration) remains<sup> </sup>supplemented by fantasizing. What<sup> </sup>this means is that<sup> </sup>the "normal" human sexual<sup> </sup>act has the structure<sup> </sup>of double masturbation; each<sup> </sup>participant is masturbating with<sup> </sup>a real partner. However,<sup> </sup>the gap between the<sup> </sup>raw reality of copulation<sup> </sup>and its fantasmatic supplement<sup> </sup>can no longer be<sup> </sup>closed; all variations and<sup> </sup>displacements of sexual practices<sup> </sup>that follow are so<sup> </sup>many desperate attempts to<sup> </sup>restore the balance of<sup> </sup>the two. The dialectical<sup> </sup>"progress" thus first goes<sup> </sup>through a series of<sup> </sup>variations with regard to<sup> </sup>the relationship between face,<sup> </sup>sexual organs, and other<sup> </sup>bodily parts and the<sup> </sup>modes of their respective<sup> </sup>uses; the organ remains<sup> </sup>phallus, but the opening<sup> </sup>to be penetrated changes<sup> </sup>(anus, mouth). Then, in<sup> </sup>a kind of "negation<sup> </sup>of negation," not only<sup> </sup>the object to be<sup> </sup>penetrated changes but the<sup> </sup>totality of the person<sup> </sup>who is the partner<sup> </sup>passes into its opposite<sup> </sup>(homosexuality). In a further<sup> </sup>development, the goal itself<sup> </sup>is no longer orgasm<sup> </sup>(fetishism). Fist-fucking introduces into<sup> </sup>this series an impossible<sup> </sup>synthesis of the hand<sup> </sup>(the organ of instrumental<sup> </sup>activity, of hard work)<sup> </sup>and vagina (the organ<sup> </sup>of "spontaneous" passive generation).<sup> </sup>The fist (focus of<sup> </sup>purposeful work, the hand<sup> </sup>as the most tightly<sup> </sup>controlled and trained part<sup> </sup>of our body) replaces<sup> </sup>phallus (the organ out<sup> </sup>of our conscious control<sup> </sup>par excellence, since its<sup> </sup>erection comes and goes<sup> </sup>independently of our will)<sup> </sup>in a kind of<sup> </sup>correlate to somebody who<sup> </sup>approaches a state that<sup> </sup>should emerge "spontaneously" in<sup> </sup>a well-planned, instrumental way<sup> </sup>(say, a poet who<sup> </sup>constructs his poems in<sup> </sup>a "rational" way is<sup> </sup>a poetic fist-fucker). There<sup> </sup>are, of course, further<sup> </sup>variations here that call<sup> </sup>for their speculative deduction:<sup> </sup>in masculine masturbation, vagina,<sup> </sup>the ultimate passive organ,<sup> </sup>is substituted by hand,<sup> </sup>the ultimate active organ<sup> </sup>making the phallus itself<sup> </sup>passive. Furthermore, when the<sup> </sup>phallus penetrates the anus,<sup> </sup>we obtain the correct<sup> </sup>insight into the speculative<sup> </sup>identity of excretion and<sup> </sup>insemination, the highest and<sup> </sup>the lowest. There is<sup> </sup>no time to explore<sup> </sup>here further variations to<sup> </sup>be deduced: doing it<sup> </sup>with an animal, with<sup> </sup>a machine or doll;<sup> </sup>doing it with many<sup> </sup>partners; sadism and masochism,<sup> </sup>and so on. The<sup> </sup>main point is that<sup> </sup>the very "progress" from<sup> </sup>one to another form<sup> </sup>is motivated by the<sup> </sup>structural imbalance of sexual<sup> </sup>relationship (Lacan's <i>il n'y a pas de rapport sexuel</i>), which<sup> </sup>condemns any sexual practice<sup> </sup>to eternal oscillation between<sup> </sup>the "spontaneous" pathos of<sup> </sup>self-obliteration and the logic<sup> </sup>of external ritual (following<sup> </sup>the rules). The final<sup> </sup>outcome is thus that<sup> </sup>sexuality is <i>the</i> domain<sup> </sup>of "spurious infinity" whose<sup> </sup>logic, brought to an<sup> </sup>extreme, cannot but engender<sup> </sup>tasteless excesses like those<sup> </sup>of "spermathon" contests: how<sup> </sup>many men can a<sup> </sup>woman bring to orgasm<sup> </sup>in an hour, and<sup> </sup>so on. For a<sup> </sup>true philosopher, there are<sup> </sup>more interesting things in<sup> </sup>the world than sex.<sup> </sup></p>
<p>&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;What<sup> </sup>accounts for the weird<sup> </sup>(if not, for some<sup> </sup>at least, tasteless) character<sup> </sup>of this exercise is<sup> </sup>not the reference to<sup> </sup>sexual practices as such<sup> </sup>but the short circuit<sup> </sup>between two spheres that<sup> </sup>are usually perceived as<sup> </sup>incompatible, as moving at<sup> </sup>ontologically different levels, that<sup> </sup>of sublime philosophical speculation<sup> </sup>and that of the<sup> </sup>details of sexual practices.<sup> </sup>Even if there is<sup> </sup>nothing that, a priori,<sup> </sup>prohibits the application of<sup> </sup>the Hegelian conceptual machinery<sup> </sup>to sexual practices, it<sup> </sup>nonetheless appears that the<sup> </sup>entire exercise is somehow<sup> </sup>meaningless, a (rather bad)<sup> </sup>joke. The unpleasant, weird<sup> </sup>effect of such short<sup> </sup>circuits signals that they<sup> </sup>play a symptomal role<sup> </sup>in our symbolic universes.<sup> </sup>They render palpable the<sup> </sup>implicit, tacit prohibitions on<sup> </sup>which these universes rely.<sup> </sup>One practices concrete universality<sup> </sup>by way of confronting<sup> </sup>a universality with its<sup> </sup>"unbearable" example. Of course,<sup> </sup>Hegelian dialectics can be<sup> </sup>used to analyze anything;<sup> </sup>nonetheless, one is tacitly<sup> </sup>summoned not to practice<sup> </sup>it on sexuality, as<sup> </sup>if this move would<sup> </sup>make ridiculous the very<sup> </sup>notion of dialectical analysis.<sup> </sup>Of course, all people<sup> </sup>are equal, but, nonetheless,<sup> </sup>one is tacitly summoned<sup> </sup>to treat some of<sup> </sup>them as "less equal,"<sup> </sup>as if asserting their<sup> </sup>full equality would undermine<sup> </sup>the very notion of<sup> </sup>equality.<sup> </sup></p>
<p>&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;This, then, is the<sup> </sup>nontrivial sense in which<sup> </sup>all of us are<sup> </sup>slandered, by neoconservatives as<sup> </sup>well as by the<sup> </sup>newly appointed guardians of<sup> </sup>universal reason, as those<sup> </sup>who undermine the very<sup> </sup>ethical fundaments of our<sup> </sup>societies. And this slandered<sup> </sup>group, including some who<sup> </sup>are not even on<sup> </sup>speaking terms, from Gilles<sup> </sup>Deleuze to Alain Badiou,<sup> </sup>are engaged in the<sup> </sup>same task of <i>practicing concrete universality</i>.<sup> </sup></p>
<br><a name="fn1"></a><font size="-1">&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;<a href="#cfn1">1</a>. Andrej<sup> </sup>Capuder, "Vino in most,"<sup> </sup><i>Demokracija</i> (Ljubljana), 9 Dec.<sup> </sup>2004, p. 9; trans.<sup> </sup>mine. Incidentally, does this<sup> </sup>"where there is a<sup> </sup>high-rise building, a bin<sup> </sup>Laden should come" not<sup> </sup>sound like a new<sup> </sup>politicized version of Freud's<sup> </sup>"wo es war soll<sup> </sup>ich werden" (Sigmund Freud,<sup> </sup><i>New Introductory Lectures on Psycho-Analysis,</i> in <i>The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud,</i> trans.<sup> </sup>and ed. James Strachey,<sup> </sup>24 vols. [London, 1953<img src="/ucp-entities/ndash.gif" alt="–" align="bottom" border="0">74],<sup> </sup>22:80)?<sup> </sup></font>
<br><a name="fn2"></a><font size="-1">&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;<a href="#cfn2">2</a>. Kevin B. MacDonald, <i>The Culture of Critique: An Evolutionary Analysis of Jewish Involvement in Twentieth-Century Intellectual and Political Movements</i><sup> </sup>(Westport, Conn., 1998), p.<sup> </sup>169; hereafter abbreviated <i>CC.</i><sup> </sup></font><br><a name="fn3"></a><font size="-1">&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;<a href="#cfn3">3</a>. Richard<sup> </sup>Wolin, <i>The Seduction of Unreason: The Intellectual Romance with Fascism from Nietzsche to Postmodernism</i> (Princeton, N.J.,<sup> </sup>2004), p. 23. See<sup> </sup>Georg Lukács, <i>Die Zerstörung der Vernunft</i> (Berlin,<sup> </sup>1953); trans. under the<sup> </sup>title <i>The Destruction of Reason,</i> by Peter<sup> </sup>Palmer (Atlantic Highlands, N.J.,<sup> </sup>1980).<sup> </sup></font>
<br><a name="fn4"></a><font size="-1">&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;<a href="#cfn4">4</a>. The same line of<sup> </sup>attack was brought to<sup> </sup>its extreme by Jörg<sup> </sup>Lau in Germany, who,<sup> </sup>after the weird claim<sup> </sup>that I celebrate the<sup> </sup>9/11 attack as the<sup> </sup>proper Lacanian political act,<sup> </sup>as the intervention in<sup> </sup>the Real which breaks<sup> </sup>the spell of capitalist<sup> </sup>ideological hallucinations, ends up<sup> </sup>by directly characterizing me<sup> </sup>as a pathological person;<sup> </sup>there is, in me,<sup> </sup>"etwas Verkommenes, geistig Verwahrlostes"<sup> </sup>(Jörg Lau, "Auf der<sup> </sup>Suche nach dem guten<sup> </sup>Terror: Über Slavoj <img src="/ucp-entities/Zcaron.gif" alt="&amp;Zcaron;" align="bottom" border="0">i<img src="/ucp-entities/zcaron.gif" alt="&amp;zcaron;" align="bottom" border="0">ek,"<sup> </sup><i>Merkur</i> 2 [Feb. 2003]:<sup> </sup>162). Is it necessary<sup> </sup>to add that I<sup> </sup>was not able to<sup> </sup>answer these defamations in<sup> </sup>any German printed medium?<sup> </sup></font>
<br><a name="fn5"></a><font size="-1">&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;<a href="#cfn5">5</a>. Wolin,<sup> </sup><i>The Seduction of Unreason,</i> p. 307.<sup> </sup></font><br><a name="fn6"></a><font size="-1">&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;<a href="#cfn6">6</a>. Slavoj <img src="/ucp-entities/Zcaron.gif" alt="&amp;Zcaron;" align="bottom" border="0">i<img src="/ucp-entities/zcaron.gif" alt="&amp;zcaron;" align="bottom" border="0">ek,<sup> </sup><i>Welcome to the Desert of the Real</i> (London, 2002), pp.<sup> </sup>51<img src="/ucp-entities/ndash.gif" alt="–" align="bottom" border="0">52.<sup> </sup></font>
<br><a name="fn7"></a><font size="-1">&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;<a href="#cfn7">7</a>. See Jacques Derrida, <i>Acts of Religion,</i><sup> </sup>trans. Samuel Weber et<sup> </sup>al., ed. Gil Anidjar<sup> </sup>(New York, 2002).<sup> </sup></font><br><a name="fn8"></a><font size="-1">&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;<a href="#cfn8">8</a>. Derrida, <i>Specters of Marx: The State of the Debt, the Work of Mourning, and the New International,</i><sup> </sup>trans. Peggy Kamuf (New<sup> </sup>York, 1994), pp. 64<img src="/ucp-entities/ndash.gif" alt="–" align="bottom" border="0">65.<sup> </sup></font>
<br><a name="fn9"></a><font size="-1">&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;<a href="#cfn9">9</a>. See<sup> </sup>Derrida, "Faith and Knowledge:<sup> </sup>The Two Sources of<sup> </sup>`Religion,'" trans. Weber, in<sup> </sup><i>Religion,</i> trans. David Webb<sup> </sup>and Weber, ed. Derrida<sup> </sup>and Gianni Vattimo (Stanford,<sup> </sup>Calif., 1998), pp. 1<img src="/ucp-entities/ndash.gif" alt="–" align="bottom" border="0">78.<sup> </sup></font>
<br><a name="fn10"></a><font size="-1">&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;<a href="#cfn10">10</a>. See<sup> </sup>Ernesto Laclau, <i>Emancipation(s)</i> (London,<sup> </sup>1995).<sup> </sup></font><br><a name="fn11"></a><font size="-1">&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;<a href="#cfn11">11</a>. Derrida, of course, developed<sup> </sup>this motif in great<sup> </sup>detail in <i>The Truth in Painting,</i> trans.<sup> </sup>Geoff Bennington and Ian<sup> </sup>McLeod (Chicago, 1987).<sup> </sup></font>
<br><a name="fn12"></a><font size="-1">&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;<a href="#cfn12">12</a>. Krzysztof Kie<img src="/ucp-entities/sacute.gif" alt="&amp;sacute;" align="bottom" border="0">lowski,<sup> </sup><i>"Workers '71," Kie<img src="/ucp-entities/sacute.gif" alt="&amp;sacute;" align="bottom" border="0">lowski on Kie<img src="/ucp-entities/sacute.gif" alt="&amp;sacute;" align="bottom" border="0">lowski,</i> ed. Danusia Stok<sup> </sup>(London, 1993), pp. 54<img src="/ucp-entities/ndash.gif" alt="–" align="bottom" border="0">55.<sup> </sup></font><br><a name="fn13"></a><font size="-1">&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;<a href="#cfn13">13</a>. Kie<img src="/ucp-entities/sacute.gif" alt="&amp;sacute;" align="bottom" border="0">lowski,<sup> </sup><i>"Station," Kie<img src="/ucp-entities/sacute.gif" alt="&amp;sacute;" align="bottom" border="0">lowski on Kie<img src="/ucp-entities/sacute.gif" alt="&amp;sacute;" align="bottom" border="0">lowski,</i> p. 86.<sup> </sup></font>
<br><a name="fn14"></a><font size="-1">&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;<a href="#cfn14">14</a>. For a<sup> </sup>more detailed account of<sup> </sup>this passage, see <img src="/ucp-entities/Zcaron.gif" alt="&amp;Zcaron;" align="bottom" border="0">i<img src="/ucp-entities/zcaron.gif" alt="&amp;zcaron;" align="bottom" border="0">ek,<sup> </sup><i>The Fright of Real Tears: Krzysztof Kie<img src="/ucp-entities/sacute.gif" alt="&amp;sacute;" align="bottom" border="0">lowski between Theory and Post-Theory</i> (London, 2001), chap.<sup> </sup>1.<sup> </sup></font>
<br><a name="fn15"></a><font size="-1">&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;<a href="#cfn15">15</a>. Rebecca Comay, "Dead Right:<sup> </sup>Hegel and the Terror,"<sup> </sup><i>South Atlantic Quarterly</i> 103 (Spring<img src="/ucp-entities/ndash.gif" alt="–" align="bottom" border="0">Summer 2004):<sup> </sup>392.<sup> </sup></font><br><a name="fn16"></a><font size="-1">&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;<a href="#cfn16">16</a>. Ibid., p. 393.<sup> </sup></font>
<br><a name="fn17"></a><font size="-1">&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;<a href="#cfn17">17</a>. Fredric Jameson,<sup> </sup><i>A Singular Modernity: Essays on the Ontology of the Present</i> (London, 2002), p.<sup> </sup>12.<sup> </sup></font><br><a name="fn18"></a><font size="-1">&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;<a href="#cfn18">18</a>. See Jacques Lacan, <i>The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psycho-Analysis,</i><sup> </sup>trans. Alan Sheridan, ed.<sup> </sup>Jacques-Alain Miller (New York,<sup> </sup>1979), p. 63.<sup> </sup></font>
<br><a name="fn19"></a><font size="-1">&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;<a href="#cfn19">19</a>. See Miller,<sup> </sup>"Angoisse constituée, angoisse constituante,"<sup> </sup><a target="_outside" href="http://www.lacan.com/jamsem2.html">http://www.lacan.com/jamsem2.html</a><sup> </sup></font><br><a name="fn20"></a><font size="-1">&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;<a href="#cfn20">20</a>. See Eric Santner, <i>On the Psychotheology of Everyday Life: Reflections on Freud and Rosenzweig</i><sup> </sup>(Chicago, 2001).<sup> </sup></font><br><a name="fn21"></a><font size="-1">&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;<a href="#cfn21">21</a>. Along the same<sup> </sup>lines, one can imagine<sup> </sup>how newly discovered notes<sup> </sup>on sexuality by Heidegger<sup> </sup>might look. The essence<sup> </sup>of woman is <i>sich anzustellen,</i><sup> </sup>to ex-pose oneself, <i>sich Anzubieten,</i><sup> </sup>to propose/offer oneself: here<sup> </sup>I am, pick me<sup> </sup>up, catch me, take<sup> </sup>me. In contrast to<sup> </sup>this stance of provocative<sup> </sup>exposure, <i>Herausforderung,</i> a man<sup> </sup>is boastfully putting himself<sup> </sup>up, parading before woman's<sup> </sup>eyes: his stance is<sup> </sup>that of <i>Sichaufstellen,</i> in<sup> </sup>the sense of <i>Sichaufspielen, Sichbruesten.</i><sup> </sup>A man <i>stellt sich auf,</i> a<sup> </sup>woman <i>stellt sich an.</i> And, from<sup> </sup>here, one can imagine<sup> </sup>a Heideggerian erotic of<sup> </sup>disclosure/withdrawal: Being provokes us<sup> </sup>in its very disclosure,<sup> </sup>it provokes us through<sup> </sup>the withdrawal in the<sup> </sup>heart of its disclosure.<sup> </sup>The essence of <i>Sichanstellen</i><sup> </sup>is the <i>Sichanstellen</i> of<sup> </sup>the essence itself, and<sup> </sup>the destiny of man<sup> </sup>is to screw things<sup> </sup>up, to fail in<sup> </sup>his attempt to respond<sup> </sup>properly to this provocative<sup> </sup>exposure. So why not<sup> </sup>take the risk of<sup> </sup>enacting Heidegger's rhetorics of<sup> </sup>reversal ("the essence of<sup> </sup>truth is the truth<sup> </sup>of the essence itself,"<sup> </sup>and so on) also<sup> </sup>apropos the notion of<sup> </sup><i>Abort</i> (toilet). The essence<sup> </sup>of abort is the<sup> </sup><i>Ab-Ort</i> (dis-placing) of the<sup> </sup>essence itself. Along the<sup> </sup>same lines, the <i>Er-Örterung</i><sup> </sup>(explaining, literally, locating at<sup> </sup>its proper place) of<sup> </sup>a poem is simultaneously<sup> </sup>its <i>Ab-Örterung</i> (flushing it<sup> </sup>down the toilet). And<sup> </sup>what about abortion itself?<sup> </sup>What if the essence<sup> </sup>of abortion <i>(Ab-Treibung, Fehl-Geburt)</i> is<sup> </sup>nothing ontic, but the<sup> </sup>abortiveness of the essence<sup> </sup>itself?<a></a><a></a><a></a><a></a><sup> </sup></font>
==Source==
Root Admin, Bots, Bureaucrats, flow-bot, oversight, Administrators, Widget editors
24,656
edits

Navigation menu