Difference between revisions of "Materialism"

From No Subject - Encyclopedia of Psychoanalysis
Jump to: navigation, search
m (A small series of spelling and formatting corrections.)
(The LinkTitles extension automatically added links to existing pages (<a rel="nofollow" class="external free" href="https://github.com/bovender/LinkTitles">https://github.com/bovender/LinkTitles</a>).)
 
Line 1: Line 1:
 
{{Top}}matérialisme{{Bottom}}
 
{{Top}}matérialisme{{Bottom}}
  
By addressing the issues of psychogenesis, the mind/body problem, etc. [[psychoanalysis]] necessarily raises ontological questions.
+
By addressing the issues of psychogenesis, the [[mind]]/body problem, etc. [[psychoanalysis]] necessarily raises [[ontological]] questions.
  
 
The questions of whether [[Freud]]'s views can be considered materialistic or not is difficult to answer.
 
The questions of whether [[Freud]]'s views can be considered materialistic or not is difficult to answer.
  
On the one hand, he insisted on the importance of the physical substratum of all mental events, in keeping with the materialist axioms of the [[science|scientists]] whom he had most respected during his studies (principally Hermann Helmholtz and Ernst Brücke). On the other hand, he opposed Charcot's attempts to explain all [[hysterical]] [[symptoms]] by reference to lesions in the brain, distinguished psychical reality from material reality, and constantly emphasized the role of experience rather than heredity in the aetiology of nervous illness.
+
On the one hand, he insisted on the importance of the [[physical]] substratum of all [[mental]] events, in keeping with the materialist axioms of the [[science|scientists]] whom he had most respected during his studies (principally Hermann Helmholtz and Ernst Brücke). On the [[other]] hand, he opposed Charcot's attempts to explain all [[hysterical]] [[symptoms]] by reference to lesions in the brain, distinguished [[psychical]] [[reality]] from material reality, and constantly emphasized the [[role]] of [[experience]] rather than heredity in the aetiology of nervous [[illness]].
  
These two trends often converge in his writings in an uneasy alliance, as in the following sentence:
+
These two trends often converge in his writings in an uneasy alliance, as in the following [[sentence]]:
  
<blockquote>Analysts are at bottom incorrigible mechanists and materialists, even though they seek to avoid robbing the mind and spirit of their still unrecognized characteristics.<ref>{{F}} 1941d. (1921). [[SE]] XVIII p.179</ref></blockquote>
+
<blockquote>[[Analysts]] are at bottom incorrigible mechanists and materialists, even though they seek to avoid robbing the mind and spirit of their still unrecognized characteristics.<ref>{{F}} 1941d. (1921). [[SE]] XVIII p.179</ref></blockquote>
  
 
--
 
--
  
[[Lacan]] too presents himself as a [[materialism|materialist]]; in 1936 he criticizes associationist psychology for not living up to its purported materialism, and in 1964 he argues that [[psychoanalysis]] is opposed to any form of [[philosophical]] [[idealism]].
+
[[Lacan]] too presents himself as a [[materialism|materialist]]; in 1936 he criticizes associationist [[psychology]] for not [[living]] up to its purported materialism, and in 1964 he argues that [[psychoanalysis]] is opposed to any [[form]] of [[philosophical]] [[idealism]].
  
 
--
 
--
  
However, as with [[Freud]], [[Lacan]]'s declarations of [[materialism]] are highly complex. It is clear in [[Lacan]]'s earliest statements on the subject that he conceives of [[materialism]] in a very particular way. In 1936, for example, he argues that [[materialism]] does not imply a rejection of the categories of intentionality and meaning, <ref>{{Ec}} p. 76-8</ref> and he rejects the simplistic idea of 'matter' as "a naive form which has been left behind by authentic materialism."<ref>{{Ec}} p.90</ref>
+
However, as with [[Freud]], [[Lacan]]'s declarations of [[materialism]] are highly [[complex]]. It is clear in [[Lacan]]'s earliest statements on the [[subject]] that he conceives of [[materialism]] in a very [[particular]] way. In 1936, for example, he argues that [[materialism]] does not imply a [[rejection]] of the [[categories]] of [[intentionality]] and [[meaning]], <ref>{{Ec}} p. 76-8</ref> and he rejects the simplistic [[idea]] of 'matter' as "a naive form which has been [[left]] behind by authentic materialism."<ref>{{Ec}} p.90</ref>
  
In 1946 he repeatedly criticizes the crude form of [[materialism]] which regards thought as a mere "epiphenomenon."<ref>{{Ec}} p.159</ref> And in 1956 he distinguishes between a "naturalist materialism" and a "Freudian materialism".<ref>{{Ec}} p.465-6</ref>
+
In 1946 he repeatedly criticizes the crude form of [[materialism]] which regards [[thought]] as a mere "epiphenomenon."<ref>{{Ec}} p.159</ref> And in 1956 he distinguishes between a "naturalist materialism" and a "[[Freudian]] materialism".<ref>{{Ec}} p.465-6</ref>
  
It is clear, then, that [[Lacan]] does not subscribe to a kind of [[materialism]] which reduces all [[cause|causation]] to a crude economic determinism which regards all cultural phenomena (including [[language]]) as a mere superstructure,"<ref>{{E}} p.125</ref> and argues that [[language]] "is something material."<ref>{{S2}} p.82</ref>
+
It is clear, then, that [[Lacan]] does not subscribe to a kind of [[materialism]] which reduces all [[cause|causation]] to a crude [[economic]] [[determinism]] which regards all [[cultural]] phenomena (including [[language]]) as a mere superstructure,"<ref>{{E}} p.125</ref> and argues that [[language]] "is something material."<ref>{{S2}} p.82</ref>
  
 
On these grounds he declares that the importance he attributes to [[language]] is perfectly compatible with historical [[materialism]].<ref>{{Ec}} p.875-6</ref>
 
On these grounds he declares that the importance he attributes to [[language]] is perfectly compatible with historical [[materialism]].<ref>{{Ec}} p.875-6</ref>
Line 29: Line 29:
 
[[Lacan]]'s [[materialism]] is thus a [[materialism]] of the [[signifier]]:
 
[[Lacan]]'s [[materialism]] is thus a [[materialism]] of the [[signifier]]:
  
<blockquote>"the point of view I am trying to maintain before you involves a certain materialism of the elements in question, in the sense that the signifiers are well and truly embodied, and materialized."<ref>{{S3}} p.289</ref></blockquote>
+
<blockquote>"the point of view I am trying to maintain before you involves a certain materialism of the elements in question, in the [[sense]] that the [[signifiers]] are well and truly embodied, and materialized."<ref>{{S3}} p.289</ref></blockquote>
  
 
However, the materiality of the [[signifier]] does not refer to a tangible inscription but to its indivisibility:
 
However, the materiality of the [[signifier]] does not refer to a tangible inscription but to its indivisibility:
  
<blockquote>"But if we have insisted firstly on the materiality of the signifier, this materiality is singular in many ways, the first of which is that the signifier does not withstand partition."<ref>{{Ec}} p.24</ref></blockquote>
+
<blockquote>"But if we have insisted firstly on the materiality of the signifier, this materiality is [[singular]] in many ways, the first of which is that the signifier does not withstand partition."<ref>{{Ec}} p.24</ref></blockquote>
  
The [[signifier]] in its material dimension, the real aspect of the [[signifier]], is the [[letter]].
+
The [[signifier]] in its material [[dimension]], the [[real]] aspect of the [[signifier]], is the [[letter]].
  
It is [[Lacan]]'s "[[materialism|materialism of the signifier]]" which leads him to give "a materialist definition of the phenomenon of consciousness."<ref>{{S2}} p. 40-52</ref>
+
It is [[Lacan]]'s "[[materialism|materialism of the signifier]]" which leads him to give "a materialist definition of the phenomenon of [[consciousness]]."<ref>{{S2}} p. 40-52</ref>
  
 
--
 
--
  
[[Lacan]]'s claims that his theory of the [[signifier]] is a materialist theory are disputed by [[Derrida]], who argues that [[Lacan]]'s concept of the [[letter]] betrays an implicit idealism.<ref>Derrida. 1975.</ref>
+
[[Lacan]]'s claims that his [[theory]] of the [[signifier]] is a materialist theory are disputed by [[Derrida]], who argues that [[Lacan]]'s [[concept]] of the [[letter]] betrays an implicit idealism.<ref>Derrida. 1975.</ref>
  
  

Latest revision as of 19:14, 20 May 2019

French: matérialisme

By addressing the issues of psychogenesis, the mind/body problem, etc. psychoanalysis necessarily raises ontological questions.

The questions of whether Freud's views can be considered materialistic or not is difficult to answer.

On the one hand, he insisted on the importance of the physical substratum of all mental events, in keeping with the materialist axioms of the scientists whom he had most respected during his studies (principally Hermann Helmholtz and Ernst Brücke). On the other hand, he opposed Charcot's attempts to explain all hysterical symptoms by reference to lesions in the brain, distinguished psychical reality from material reality, and constantly emphasized the role of experience rather than heredity in the aetiology of nervous illness.

These two trends often converge in his writings in an uneasy alliance, as in the following sentence:

Analysts are at bottom incorrigible mechanists and materialists, even though they seek to avoid robbing the mind and spirit of their still unrecognized characteristics.[1]

--

Lacan too presents himself as a materialist; in 1936 he criticizes associationist psychology for not living up to its purported materialism, and in 1964 he argues that psychoanalysis is opposed to any form of philosophical idealism.

--

However, as with Freud, Lacan's declarations of materialism are highly complex. It is clear in Lacan's earliest statements on the subject that he conceives of materialism in a very particular way. In 1936, for example, he argues that materialism does not imply a rejection of the categories of intentionality and meaning, [2] and he rejects the simplistic idea of 'matter' as "a naive form which has been left behind by authentic materialism."[3]

In 1946 he repeatedly criticizes the crude form of materialism which regards thought as a mere "epiphenomenon."[4] And in 1956 he distinguishes between a "naturalist materialism" and a "Freudian materialism".[5]

It is clear, then, that Lacan does not subscribe to a kind of materialism which reduces all causation to a crude economic determinism which regards all cultural phenomena (including language) as a mere superstructure,"[6] and argues that language "is something material."[7]

On these grounds he declares that the importance he attributes to language is perfectly compatible with historical materialism.[8]

--

Lacan's materialism is thus a materialism of the signifier:

"the point of view I am trying to maintain before you involves a certain materialism of the elements in question, in the sense that the signifiers are well and truly embodied, and materialized."[9]

However, the materiality of the signifier does not refer to a tangible inscription but to its indivisibility:

"But if we have insisted firstly on the materiality of the signifier, this materiality is singular in many ways, the first of which is that the signifier does not withstand partition."[10]

The signifier in its material dimension, the real aspect of the signifier, is the letter.

It is Lacan's "materialism of the signifier" which leads him to give "a materialist definition of the phenomenon of consciousness."[11]

--

Lacan's claims that his theory of the signifier is a materialist theory are disputed by Derrida, who argues that Lacan's concept of the letter betrays an implicit idealism.[12]


See Also

References

  1. Freud, Sigmund. 1941d. (1921). SE XVIII p.179
  2. Lacan, Jacques. Écrits. Paris: Seuil, 1966. p. 76-8
  3. Lacan, Jacques. Écrits. Paris: Seuil, 1966. p.90
  4. Lacan, Jacques. Écrits. Paris: Seuil, 1966. p.159
  5. Lacan, Jacques. Écrits. Paris: Seuil, 1966. p.465-6
  6. Lacan, Jacques. Écrits: A Selection. Trans. Alan Sheridan. London: Tavistock Publications, 1977. p.125
  7. Lacan, Jacques. The Seminar. Book II. The Ego in Freud's Theory and in the Technique of Psychoanalysis, 1954-55. Trans. Sylvana Tomaselli. New York: Nortion; Cambridge: Cambridge Unviersity Press, 1988. p.82
  8. Lacan, Jacques. Écrits. Paris: Seuil, 1966. p.875-6
  9. Lacan, Jacques. The Seminar. Book III. The Psychoses, 1955-56. Trans. Russell Grigg. London: Routledge, 1993. p.289
  10. Lacan, Jacques. Écrits. Paris: Seuil, 1966. p.24
  11. Lacan, Jacques. The Seminar. Book II. The Ego in Freud's Theory and in the Technique of Psychoanalysis, 1954-55. Trans. Sylvana Tomaselli. New York: Nortion; Cambridge: Cambridge Unviersity Press, 1988. p. 40-52
  12. Derrida. 1975.